A Brief Outline of an Approach to Anthroposophy
If one observes how, up to the present time, the philosophical world
conceptions take form, one can see undercurrents in the search and
endeavor of the various thinkers, of which they themselves are not
aware but by which they are instinctively moved. In these currents
there are forces at work that give direction and often specific form
to the ideas expressed by these thinkers. Although they do not want to
focus their attention on the forces directly, what they have to say
often appears as if driven by hidden forces, which they are unwilling
to acknowledge and from which they recoil. Forces of this kind live in
the thought worlds of Dilthey, Eucken and Cohen. They are led by
cognitive powers by which they are unconsciously dominated but that do
not find a conscious development within their thought structures.
Security and certainty of knowledge is being sought in many
philosophical systems, and Kant's ideas are more or less taken as its
point of departure. The outlook of natural science determines,
consciously or unconsciously, the process of thought formation. But it
is dimly felt by many that the source of knowledge of the external
world must be sought in the self-conscious soul. Almost all of these
thinkers are dominated by the question: How can the self-conscious
soul be led to regard its inner experiences as a true manifestation of
reality? The ordinary world of sense perception has become
illusion because the self-conscious ego has, in the course
of philosophical development, found itself more and more isolated with
its subjective experiences. It has arrived at the point where it
regards even sense perception merely as inner experience that is
powerless to assure being and permanence for them in the world of
reality. It is felt how much depends on finding a point of support
within the self-conscious ego. But the search stimulated by this
feeling only leads to conceptions that do not provide the means of
submerging with the ego into a world that provides satisfactory
support for existence.
To explain this fact, one must look at the attitude toward the reality
of the external world taken by a soul that has detached itself from
that reality in the course of its philosophical development. This soul
feels itself surrounded by a world of which it first becomes aware
through the senses. But then it also becomes conscious of its own
activity, of its own inner creative experience. The soul feels, as an
irrefutable truth, that no light, no color can be revealed without the
eye's sensitivity for light and color. Thus, it becomes aware of
something creative in this activity of the eye. But if the eye
produces the color by its spontaneous creation, as it must be assumed
in such a philosophy, the question arises: Where do I find something
that exists in itself, that does not owe its existence to my own
creative power? If even the manifestations of the senses are nothing
but results of the activity of the soul, must this not be true to even
a higher degree with our thinking, through which we strive for
conceptions of a true reality? Is this thinking not condemned to
produce pictures that spring from the character of the soul life but
can never provide a sure approach to the sources of existence?
Questions of this kind emerge everywhere in the development of modern
philosophy.
It will be impossible to find the way out of the confusion resulting
from these questions as long as the belief is maintained that the
world revealed by the senses constitutes a complete, finished and
self-dependent reality that must be investigated in order to know its
inner nature. The human soul can arrive at its insights only through a
spontaneous inner creativity. This conviction has been described in a
previous chapter of this book, The World as Illusion, and
in connection with the presentation of Hamerling's thoughts. Having
reached this conviction, it is difficult to overcome a certain impasse
of knowledge as long as one thinks that the world of the senses
contains the real basis of its existence within itself and that
one therefore has to copy with the inner activity of the soul what
lies outside.
This impasse will be overcome only by accepting the fact that, by its
very nature, sense perception does not present a finished
self-contained reality, but an unfinished, incomplete reality, or a
half-reality, as it were.
As soon as one presupposes that a full reality is gained through
perceptions of the sensory world, one is forever prevented from
finding the answer to the question: What has the creative mind to add
to this reality in the act of cognition? By necessity one shall have
to sustain the Kantian option: Man must consider his knowledge to be
the inner product of his own mind; he cannot regard it as a process
that is capable of revealing a true reality. If reality lies
outside the soul, then the soul cannot produce anything that
corresponds to this reality, and the result is merely a product of the
soul's own organization.
The situation is entirely changed as soon as it is realized that the
human soul does not deviate from reality in its creative effort for
knowledge, but that prior to any cognitive activity the soul conjures
up a world that is not real. Man is so placed in the world that
by the nature of his being he changes things from what they really
are. Hamerling is partly right when he says:
Certain stimuli produce the odor within our organ of smell. The rose,
therefore, has no fragrance if nobody smells it. . . . If this, dear
reader, does not seem plausible to you, if your mind stirs like a shy
horse when it is confronted with this fact, do not bother to read
another line; leave this book and all others that deal with
philosophical things unread, for you lack the ability that is
necessary for this purpose, that is, to apprehend a fact without bias
and to adhere to it in your thoughts. (Compare pages
of this volume.)
How the sensory world appears when man is confronted with it,
depends without a doubt on the nature of the soul. Does it not follow
then that this appearance of the world is a product of man's soul?
An unbiased observation shows, however, that the unreal character
of the external sense world is caused by the fact that when man is
directly confronted by things of the world, he suppresses something
that really belongs to them. If he unfolds a creative inner life that
lifts from the depths of his soul the forces that lie dormant in them,
he adds something to the part perceived by the senses and thereby
turns a half-reality to its entirety. It is due to the nature of the
soul that, at its first contact with things, it extinguishes
something that belongs to them. For this reason, things appear to
the senses not as they are in reality but as they are modified by the
soul. Their delusive character (or their mere appearance) is caused by
the fact that the soul has deprived them of something that really
belongs to them.
Inasmuch as man does not merely observe things, he adds something to
them in the process of knowledge that reveals their full reality. The
mind does not add anything to things in the process of cognition that
would have to be considered as an unreal element, but prior to the
process of knowledge it has deprived these things of something that
belongs to their true reality. It will be the task of philosophy to
realize that the world accessible to man is an illusion
before it is approached in the process of cognition. This
process, however, leads the way toward a full understanding of
reality. The knowledge that man creates during the process of
cognition seems to be an inner manifestation of the soul only because
he must, before the act of cognition, reject what comes from the
nature of things. He cannot see at first the real nature of things
when he encounters them in mere observation. In the process of
knowledge he unveils what was first concealed. If he regards as a
reality what he had at first perceived, he will now realize that he
has added the results of his cognitive activity to reality. As soon as
he recognizes that what was apparently produced by himself has to be
sought in the things themselves, that he merely failed to see it
previously, he will then find that the process of knowing is a real
process by which the soul progressively unites with world reality.
Through it, it expands its inner isolated experience to the experience
of the world.
In a short work,
Truth and Science,
published in 1892, the
author of the present book made a first attempt to prove
philosophically what has been briefly described. Perspectives are
indicated in this book that are necessary to the philosophy of the
present age if it is to overcome the obstacles it has encountered in
its modern development. A philosophical point of view is outlined in
this essay in the following words:
The initial form in which reality confronts the ego is not its true
manifestation but the final form, which the ego fashions out of it,
is. The first form is altogether without significance for the
objective world; it is of importance only as a basis for the processes
of cognition. Therefore, it is not the form of the world that is
presented by theory that must be considered subjective but the one the
ego encounters initially as in mere perception.
It is not due to the objects that they are given to us at first
without their corresponding concept, but to our mental organization.
Our whole being functions in such a way that from every real thing the
relevant elements come to us from two sources, from perceiving and
from thinking. The way I am organized for apprehending the things has
nothing to do with the nature of the things themselves. The gap
between perceiving and thinking exists only from the moment that I, as
a spectator, confront the things.
And later on it is stated:
The percept is that part of reality that is given objectively; the
concept the part that is given subjectively, through intuition. Our
mental organization tears the reality apart into these two factors.
The one factor presents itself to perception, the other to intuition.
Only the union of the two, that is, the percept fitting systematically
into the universe, constitutes the full reality. If we take mere
percepts by themselves we have no reality but rather disconnected
chaos. If we take by itself the law and order connecting the percepts
then we have nothing but abstract concepts. Reality is not contained
in the abstract concept. It is, however, contained in thoughtful
observation, which does not one-sidedly consider either concept or
percept alone, but rather the union of the two.
In accepting this point of view we shall be able to think of mental
life and of reality as united in the self-conscious ego. This is the
conception toward which philosophical development has tended since the
Greek era and that has shown its first distinctly recognizable traces
in the world conception of Goethe. The awareness arises that this
self-conscious ego does not experience itself as isolated and divorced
from the objective world, but its detachment from this world is
experienced merely as an illusion of its consciousness. This isolation
can be overcome if man gains the insight that at a certain stage of
his development he must give a provisional form to his ego in order to
suppress from his consciousness the forces that unite him with the
world. If these forces exerted their influences in his consciousness
without interruption, he would never have developed a strong,
independent self-consciousness. He would be incapable of experiencing
himself as a self-conscious ego. The development of
self-consciousness, therefore, actually depends on the fact that the
mind is given the opportunity to perceive the world without that part
of reality that is extinguished by the self-conscious ego prior
to an act of cognition.
The world forces belonging to this part of reality withdraw into
obscurity in order to allow the self-conscious ego to shine forth in
full power. The ego must realize that it owes its self-knowledge to a
fact that spreads a veil over the knowledge of the world. It follows
that everything that stimulates the soul to a vigorous, energetic
experience of the ego, conceals at the same time the deeper
foundations in which this ego has its roots. All knowledge acquired by
the ordinary consciousness tends to strengthen the self-conscious ego.
Man feels himself as a self-conscious ego through the fact that he
perceives an external world with his senses, that he experiences
himself as being outside this external world and that, at a certain
stage of scientific investigation, he feels himself in relation to
this external world in such a way that it appears to him as
illusion. Were it not so, the self-conscious ego would not
emerge. If, therefore, in the act of knowledge one attempts merely to
copy what is observed before knowledge begins, one does not arrive at
a true experience of full reality, but only at an image of a
half reality.
Once this is admitted to be the situation, one can no longer look for
the answer of the riddles of philosophy within the experiences of the
soul that appear on the level of ordinary consciousness. It is the
function of this consciousness to strengthen the self-conscious ego.
To achieve this it must cast a veil over the connection of the ego
with the objective world, and it therefore cannot show how the soul is
connected with the true world. This explains why a method of knowledge
that applies the means of the natural scientific or similar modes of
conception must always arrive at a point where its efforts break down.
This failing of many modern thinkers has previously been pointed out
in this book, for, in the final analysis, all scientific endeavor
employs the same mode of thinking that serves to detach the
self-conscious ego from the true reality. The strength and greatness
of modern science, especially of natural science, is based on the
unrestrained application of this method.
Several philosophers such as Dilthey, Eucken and others, direct
philosophical investigation toward the self-observation of the soul.
But what they observe are those experiences of the soul that form the
basis for the self-conscious ego. Thus, they do not penetrate to the
sources in which the experiences of the soul originate. These sources
cannot be found where the soul first observes itself on the level of
ordinary consciousness. If the soul is to reach these sources, it must
go beyond this ordinary consciousness. It must experience something in
itself that ordinary consciousness cannot give to it. To ordinary
thinking, such an experience appears at first like sheer nonsense. The
soul is to experience itself knowingly in an element without
carrying its consciousness into that element. One is to transcend
consciousness and yet be conscious! But in spite of all this, we shall
either continue to get nowhere, or we shall have to open new aspects
that will reveal the above mentioned absurdity to be only
apparently so since it really indicates the direction in which we must
look for help to solve the riddles of philosophy.
One will have to recognize that the path into the inner region
of the soul must be entirely different from the one that is
taken by many philosophies of modern times. As long as soul
experiences are taken the way they present themselves to ordinary
consciousness, one will not reach down into the depths of the soul.
One will be left merely with what these depths release. Such is the
case with Eucken's world conception. It is necessary to penetrate
below the surface of the soul. This is, however, not possible by means
of the ordinary experiences. The strength of these rests precisely in
the fact that they remain in the realm of the ordinary consciousness.
The means to penetrate deeper into the soul can be found if one
directs one's attention to something that is, to be sure, also at work
in the ordinary consciousness, but does not enter it while it is
active.
While man thinks, his consciousness is focused on his thoughts. He
wants to conceive something by means of these thoughts; he wants to
think correctly in the ordinary sense. He can, however, also direct
his attention to something else. He can concentrate his attention on
the activity of thinking as such. He can, for instance, place into the
center of his consciousness a thought that refers to nothing external,
a thought that is conceived like a symbol that has no connection to
something external. It is now possible to hold onto such a thought for
a certain length of time. One can be entirely absorbed by the
concentration on this thought. The important thing with this exercise
is not that one lives in thoughts but that one experiences the
activity of thinking. In this way, the soul breaks away from an
activity in which it is engaged in ordinary thinking.
If such an inner exercise is continued long enough, it will become
gradually apparent to the soul that it has now become involved in
experiences that will separate it from all those processes of thinking
and ideation that are bound to the physical organs. A similar result
can be obtained from the activities of feeling and willing and even
for sensation, the perception of external things. One can only be
successful with this approach if one is not afraid to admit to oneself
that self-knowledge cannot be gained by mere introspection, but by
concentrating on the inner life that can be revealed only through
these exercises. Through continued practice of the soul, that is, by
holding the attention on the inner activity of thinking, feeling and
willing, it is possible for these experiences to become
condensed. In this state of condensation they
reveal their inner nature, which cannot be perceived in the ordinary
consciousness. It is through such exercises that one discovers how our
soul forces must be so attenuated or weakened in producing
our ordinary form of consciousness, that they become imperceptible in
this state of attenuation. The soul exercises referred to
consist in the unlimited increase of faculties that are also
known to the ordinary consciousness but never reach such a state of
concentration. The faculties are those of attention and of
loving surrender to the content of the soul's experience. To
attain the indicated aim, these abilities must be increased to such a
degree that they function as entirely new soul forces.
If one proceeds in this manner, one arrives at a real inner experience
that by its very nature is independent of bodily conditions. This is a
life of the spirit that must not be confused with what Dilthey and
Eucken call the spiritual world. For what they call the
spiritual world is, after all, experienced by man when he depends on
his physical organs. The spiritual life that is here referred to does
not exist for a soul that is bound to the body.
One of the first experiences that follows the attainment of this new
spiritual life is a true insight into the nature of the ordinary
mental life. This is actually not produced by the body but proceeds
outside the body. When I see a color, when I hear a sound, I
experience the color and the sound not as a result of my body, but I
am connected with the color, with the sound, as a self-conscious ego,
outside my body. My body has the task to function in a way that can be
compared with the action of a mirror. If, in my ordinary
consciousness, I only have a mental connection with a color, I cannot
perceive it because of the nature of this consciousness, just as I
cannot see my own face when I look out into space. But if I look into
a mirror, I perceive this face as part of a body. Unless I stand in
front of the mirror, I am the body and experience myself as
such. Standing in front of the mirror, I perceive my body as a
reflection. It is like this also with our sense perceptions, although
we must, of course, be aware of the insufficiency of the analogy. I
live with a color outside my body; through the activity of my
body, that is, my eye and my nervous system, this color is transformed
for me into a conscious perception. The human body is not the producer
of perceptions and of mental life in general, but a mirroring device
of psychic and spiritual processes that take place outside the body.
Such a view places the theory of knowledge on a promising basis. In a
lecture called,
The Psychological Foundations and Epistemological Position of Spiritual Science,
delivered before the Philosophical
Congress in Bologna on April 18, 1911, the author of this book gave
the following account of a view that was then forming in his mind.
On the basis of epistemology one can reach a conception of the ego
only if one does not think of it as being inside the bodily
organization and as receiving impression from outside. One
should conceive this ego as having its being within
the general order (Gesetzmässigkeit) of the things
themselves, and regard the organization of the body merely as a sort
of mirror through which the organic processes of the body reflect back
to the ego what this ego perceives outside the physical body as it
lives and weaves within the true essence of the world.
During sleep the mirror-like relation between body and soul is
interrupted; the ego lives only in the sphere of
the spirit. For the ordinary consciousness, however, mental life does
not exist as long as the body does not reflect the experiences. Sleep,
therefore, is an unconscious process. The exercises mentioned above
and other similar ones establish a consciousness that differs from the
ordinary consciousness. In this way, the faculty is developed not
merely to have purely spiritual experiences, but to
strengthen these experiences to such a degree that they become
spiritually perceptible without the aid of the body, and that they
become reflected within themselves. It is only in an experience of
this kind that the soul can obtain true self-knowledge and become
consciously aware of its own being. Real experiences that do not
belong to the sense world, but to one in which the soul weaves and has
its being, now rise in the manner in which memory brings back
experiences of the past. It is quite natural that the followers of
many modern philosophies will believe that the world that thus rises
up belongs in the realms of error, illusion, hallucination,
autosuggestion, etc. To this objection one can only answer that a
serious spiritual endeavor, working in the indicated way, will
discipline the mind to a point where it will clearly differentiate
illusion from spiritual reality, just as a healthy mind can
distinguish a product of fantasy from a concrete perception. It will
be futile to seek theoretical proofs for this spiritual world, but
such proofs also do not exist for the reality of the world of
perceptions. In both cases, actual experience is the only true
judge.
What keeps many men from undertaking the step that, according to this
view, can alone solve the riddles of philosophy, is the fear that they
might be led thereby into a realm of unclear mysticism. Unless one has
from the beginning an inclination toward unclear mysticism, one will,
in following the described path, gain access to a world of spiritual
experience that is as crystal clear as the structures of mathematical
ideas. If one is, however, inclined to seek the spiritual in the
dark unknown, in the inexplicable, one will
get nowhere, either as an adherent or as an opponent of the views
described here.
One can easily understand why these views will be rejected by
personalities who consider the methods used by natural science for
obtaining knowledge of the sense world as the only true ones. But
whoever overcomes such one-sidedness will be able to realize that the
genuinely scientific way of thinking constitutes the real basis for
the method that is here described. The ideas that have been shown in
this book to be those of the modern scientific method, present the
best subject matter for mental exercises in which the soul can immerse
itself, and on which it can concentrate in order to free itself from
its bondage to the body. Whoever uses these natural scientific ideas
in the manner that has been outlined above, will find that the
thoughts that first seem to be meant to depict only natural processes
will really set the soul free from the body. Therefore, the spiritual
science that is here referred to must be seen as a continuation of the
scientific way of thinking provided it is inwardly experienced in the
right way.
The true nature of the human soul can be experienced directly
if one seeks it in the characterized way. In the Greek era the
development of the philosophical outlook led to the birth of thought.
Later development led through the experience of thought to the
experience of the self-conscious ego. Goethe strove for experiences of
the self-conscious ego, which, although actively produced by the human
soul, at the same time place this soul in the realm of a reality that
is inaccessible to the senses. Goethe stands on this ground when he
strives for an idea of the plant that cannot be perceived by the
senses but that contains the supersensible nature of all plants,
making it possible, with the aid of this idea, to invent new plants
that would have their own life.
Hegel regarded the experience of thought as a standing in the
true essence of the world; for him the world of thoughts became
the inner essence of the world. An unbiased observation of
philosophical development shows that thought experience was, to be
sure, the element through which the self-conscious ego was to be
placed on its own foundation. But it shows also that it is necessary
to go beyond a life in mere thoughts in order to arrive at a form of
inner experience that leads beyond the ordinary consciousness. For
Hegel's thought experience still takes place within the field of this
ordinary consciousness.
In this way, a view of a reality is opened up for the soul that is
inaccessible to the senses. What is experienced in the soul through
the penetration into this reality, appears as the true entity
of the soul. How is it related to the external world that is
experienced by means of the body? The soul that has been thus freed
from its body feels itself to be weaving in an element of soul and
spirit. It knows that also in its ordinary life it is outside that
body, which merely acts like a mirror in making its experiences
perceptible. Through this experience the soul's spiritual experience
is heightened to a point where the reality of a new element is
revealed to the soul.
To Dilthey and Eucken the spiritual world is the sum total of the
cultural experiences of humanity. If this world is seen as the only
accessible spiritual world, one does not stand on a ground firm enough
to be comparable to the method of natural science. For the conception
of natural science, the world is so ordered that the physical human
being in his individual existence appears as a unit toward which all
other natural processes and beings point. The cultural world is what
is created by this human being. That world, however, is not an
individual entity of a higher nature than the individuality of the
human being.
The spiritual science that the author of this book has in mind points
to a form of experience that the soul can have independent from the
body, and in this experience an individual entity is revealed. It
emerges like a higher human nature for whom the physical man is like a
tool. The being that feels itself as set free, through spiritual
experience, from the physical body, is a spiritual human entity that
is as much at home in a spiritual world as the physical body in the
physical world. As the soul thus experiences its spiritual nature, it
is also aware of the fact that it stands in a certain relation to the
body. The body appears, on the one hand, as a cast of the spiritual
entity; it can be compared to the shell of a snail that is like a
counter-picture of the shape of the snail. On the other hand, the
spirit-soul entity appears in the body like the sum total of the
forces in the plant, which, after it has grown into leaf and blossom,
contract into the seed in order to prepare a new plant. One cannot
experience the inner spiritual man without knowing that he contains
something that will develop into a new physical man. This new human
being, while living within the physical organism, has collected forces
through experience that could not unfold as long as they were encased
in that organism. This body has, to be sure, enabled the soul to have
experiences in connection with the external world that make the inner
spiritual man different from what he was before he began life in the
physical body. But this body is, as it were, too rigidly organized
for being transformed by the inner spiritual man according to the
pattern of the new experiences. Thus there remains hidden in the human
shell a spiritual being that contains the disposition of a new man.
Thoughts such as these can only be briefly indicated here. They point
to a spiritual science that is essentially constructed after the model
of natural science. In elaborating this spiritual science one will
have to proceed more or less like the botanist when he observes a
plant, the formation of its root, the growth of its stem and its
leaves, and its development into blossom and fruit. In the fruit he
discovers the seed of the new plant-life. As he follows the
development of a plant he looks for its origin in the seed formed by
the previous plant. The investigator of spiritual science will trace
the process in which a human life, apart from its external
manifestation, develops also an inner being. He will find that
external experiences die off like the leaves and the flowers of a
plant. Within the inner being, however, he will discover a spiritual
kernel, which conceals within itself the potentiality of a new life.
In the infant entering life through birth he will see the return of a
soul that left the world previously through the gate of death. He will
learn to observe that what is handed down by heredity to the
individual man from his ancestors is merely the material that is
worked upon by the spiritual man in order to bring into physical
existence what has been prepared seedlike in a preceding life.
Seen from the viewpoint of this world conception, many facts of
psychology will appear in a new light. A great number of examples
could be mentioned here; it will suffice to point out only one. One
can observe how the human soul is transformed by experiences that
represent, in a certain sense, repetitions of earlier experiences. If
somebody has read an important book in his twentieth year and reads it
again in his fortieth, he experiences it as if he were a different
person. If he asks without bias for the reason for this fact, he will
find that what he learned from his reading twenty years previous has
continued to live in -him and has become a part of his nature. He has
within him the forces that live in the book, and he finds them again
when he rereads the book at the age of forty. The same holds true with
our life experiences. They become part of man himself. They live in
his ego. But it is also apparent that within the limits of
one life this inner strengthening of the higher man must remain in the
realm of his spirit and soul nature. Yet one can also find that this
higher human being strives to become strong enough to find expression
in his physical nature. The rigidity of the body prevents this from
happening within a single life span. But in the central core of man
there lives the potential predisposition that, together with the
fruits of one life, will form a new human life in the same way that
the seed of a new plant lives in the plant.
Moreover, it must be realized that following the entry of the soul
into an independent spirit world the results of this world are raised
into consciousness in the same way that the past rises into memory.
But these realities are seen as extending beyond the span of an
individual life. The content of my present consciousness represents
the results of my earlier physical experiences; so, too, a soul that
has gone through the indicated exercises faces the whole of its
physical experience and the particular configuration of its body as
originating from the spirit-soul nature, whose existence preceded that
of the body. This existence appears as a life in a purely spiritual
world in which the soul lived before it could develop the germinal
capacities of a preceding life into a new one. Only by closing one's
mind to the obvious possibility that the faculties of the human soul
are capable of development can one refuse to recognize the
truthfulness of a person's testimony that shows that as a result of
inner work one can really know of a spiritual world beyond the realm
of ordinary consciousness. This knowledge leads to a spiritual
apprehension of a world through which it becomes evident that the true
being of the soul lies behind ordinary experiences. It also becomes
clear that this soul being survives death just as the plant seed
survives the decay of the plant. The insight is gained that the human
soul goes through repeated lives on earth and that in between these
earthly lives it leads a purely spiritual existence.
This point of view brings reality to the assumption of a spiritual
world. The human souls themselves carry into a later cultural epoch
what they acquired in a former. One can readily observe how the inner
dispositions of the soul develop if one refrains from arbitrarily
ascribing this development merely to the laws of physical heredity. In
the spiritual world of which Eucken and Dilthey speak the later phases
of development always follow from the immediately preceding ones. Into
this sequence of events are placed human souls who bring with them the
results of their preceding lives in the form of their inner soul
disposition. They must, however, acquire in a process of learning what
developed in the earthly world of culture and civilization while they
were in a purely spiritual state of existence.
A historical account cannot do full justice to the thoughts exposed
here. I would refer anyone who seeks more information to my writings
on spiritual science. These writings attempted to give, in a general
manner, the world conception that is outlined in the present
book. Even so, I believe that it is possible to recognize from it that
this world conception rests on a serious philosophical foundation. On
this basis it strives to gain access to a world that opens up to
sense-free observation acquired by inner work.
One of the teachers of this world conception is the history of
philosophy itself. It shows that the course of philosophical thought
tends toward a conception that cannot be acquired in a state of
ordinary consciousness. The accounts of many representative thinkers
show how they attempt in various ways to comprehend the self-conscious
ego with the help of the ordinary consciousness. A theoretical
exposition of why the means of this ordinary consciousness must lead
to unsatisfactory results does not belong to a historical account. But
the historical facts show distinctly that the ordinary consciousness,
however we may look at it, cannot solve the questions it nevertheless
must raise. This final chapter was written to show why the ordinary
consciousness and the usual scientific mind lack the means to solve
such questions. This chapter was meant to describe what the
characterized world conceptions were unconsciously striving for. From
one certain point of view this last chapter no longer belongs to the
history of philosophy, but from another point of view, its
justification is quite clear. The message of this book is that a world
conception based on spiritual science is virtually demanded by the
development of modern philosophy as an answer to the questions it
raises.
To become aware of this one must consider specific instances of this
philosophical development. Franz Brentano in his Psychology
points out how philosophy was deflected from the treatment of the
deeper riddles of the soul (compare page
of this volume).
He writes, Apparent as the necessity for a restriction of the field
of investigation is in this direction, it is perhaps no more than only
apparent. David Hume was most emphatically opposed to the
metaphysicists who maintained that they had found within themselves a
carrier for all psychic conditions. He says:
For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I
always stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or
cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I can never
catch myself at any time without a perception and never can
observe anything but perceptions. When my perceptions are removed for
any time, as by sound sleep, so long am I insensible of myself
and may truly be said not to exist. (Treatise of Human Nature,
Part IV, Sect. 6.)
Hume only knows the kind of psychological observation that would
approach the soul without any inner effort. An observation of this
kind simply cannot penetrate to the nature of the soul. Brentano takes
up Hume's statement and says, This same man, Hume, nevertheless,
observes that all proofs for the immortality of the soul possess the
same power of persuasion as the opposing traditional views. But
here we must add that only faith, and not knowledge, can support
Hume's view that the soul contains nothing more than what he finds
there. For how could any continuity be guaranteed for what Hume finds
as the content of the soul? Brentano continues by saying:
Although it is obvious that a denial of a soul substance eliminates
the possibility to speak of an immortality in the proper sense of the
word, it is still not true that the question of immortality loses all
meaning if a supporting substance for psychic activity is denied.
This becomes immediately evident if one considers that, with or
without supporting substance, one cannot deny that our psychic life
here on earth has a certain continuity. If one rejects the idea of a
soul substance, one has the right to assume that this continuity does
not depend on a supporting substance. The question as to whether our
psychic life would continue after the destruction of our body will be
no less meaningful for such a thinker than it is for others. It is
really quite inconsistent if thinkers of this school reject the
essential question of immortality as meaningless also in this
important sense on the basis of the above-mentioned reason. It should
then, however, be referred to as the immortality of life rather than
that of the soul. (Brentano, Psychology from the Empirical
Standpoint, Bk. I, Chap. 1.)
This opinion of Brentano's, however, is without support if the world
conception outlined above is rejected. For where can we find grounds
for the survival of psychic phenomena after the dissolution of the
body if we want to restrict ourselves to the ordinary consciousness?
This consciousness can only last as long as its reflector, the
physical body, exists. What may survive the loss of the body cannot be
designated as substance; it must be another form of
consciousness. But this other consciousness can be discovered only
through the inner activity that frees the soul from the body. This
shows us that the soul can experience consciousness even without the
mediation of the body. Through such activity and with the help of
supersensible perception, the soul will experience the
condition of the complete loss of the body. It finds that it had been
the body, itself, that obscured that higher consciousness. While the
soul is incarnated, the body has such a strong effect on the soul that
this other consciousness cannot become active. This becomes a matter
of direct experience when the soul exercises indicated in this chapter
are successfully carried out. The soul must then consciously suppress
the forces that originate in the body and extinguish the body-free
consciousness. This extinction can no longer take place after the
dissolution of the body. It is the other consciousness, therefore,
that passes through successive lives and through the purely spiritual
existence between death and birth. From this point of view, there is
reference to a nebulous soul substance. In terms that are comparable
to ideas of natural science, the soul is shown how it continues its
existence because in one life the seed of the next is prepared, as the
seed is prepared in the plant. The present life is shown as the reason
for a future life, and the true essence of what continues when death
dissolves the body is brought to light.
Spiritual science as described here nowhere contradicts the methods of
modern natural science. But science has to admit that with its methods
one cannot gain insight into the realm of the spiritual. As soon as
the existence of a consciousness other than the ordinary one is
recognized, one will find that by it one is led to conceptions
concerning the spiritual world that will give to it a cohesion similar
to that that natural science gives to the physical world.
It will be of importance to eliminate the impression that this
spiritual science has borrowed its insights from any older form of
religion. One is easily misled to this view because the conception of
reincarnation, for instance, is a tenet of certain creeds. For the
modern investigator of spiritual science, there can be no borrowing
from such creeds. He finds that the devotion to the exercises
described above will lead to a consciousness that enters the spiritual
world. As a result of this consciousness he learns that the soul has
its standing in the spiritual world in the way previously described.
A study of the history of philosophy, beginning with the awakening of
thought in Greek civilization, indicates the way that leads to the
conviction that the true being of the soul can be found below the
surface of ordinary experience. Thinking has proved to be the educator
of the soul by leading it to the point at which it is alone with
itself. This experience of solitude strengthens the soul whereby it is
able to delve not only into its own being but also to reach into the
deeper realities of the world. The spiritual science described in this
chapter does not attempt to lead behind the world of the senses by
using the means of ordinary consciousness, such as reflection and
theorizing. It recognizes that the spiritual world must remain
concealed from that consciousness and that the soul must, through its
own inner transformation, rise into the supersensible world before it
can become conscious of it.
In this way, the insight is also gained that the origin of moral
impulses lies in the world that the soul perceives when it is free of
the body. From there also the driving forces originate that do not
stem from the physical nature of man but are meant to determine his
actions independent from this nature.
When one becomes acquainted with the fact that the ego
with its spiritual world lives outside the body and that it,
therefore, carries the experiences of the external world to the
physical body, one will find one's way to a truly spiritual
understanding of the riddle of human destiny. A man's inner life is
deeply connected with his experiences of destiny. Just consider the
state of a man at the age of thirty. The real content of his inner
being would be entirely different if he had lived a different kind of
life in his preceding years. His ego is inconceivable
without the experiences of these years. Even if they have struck him
serious blows of fate, he has become what he is through them. They
belong to the forces that are active in his ego. They do
not merely strike him from outside. As man lives in his soul and
spirit with color that is perceptible only by means of its
mirror-effect of the body, so he lives in union with his destiny. With
color he is united in his soul life, but he can only perceive it when
the body reflects it. Similarly, he becomes one with the effect of a
stroke of destiny that results from a previous earth life, but he
experiences this blow only inasmuch as the soul plunges
unconsciously into events that spring from these causes. In his
ordinary consciousness man does not know that his will is bound
up with his destiny. In his newly acquired body-free consciousness he
finds that he would be deprived of all initiative if that part of his
soul that lives in the spiritual world had not willed its entire fate,
down to the smallest details. We see that the riddles of human destiny
cannot be solved merely by theorizing about them, but only by learning
to understand how the soul grows together with its fate in an
experience that proceeds beyond the ordinary consciousness.
Thus, one will gradually realize that the causes for this or that
stroke of destiny in the present life must be sought in a previous
one. To the ordinary consciousness our fate does not appear in its
true form. It takes its course as a result of previous earthly lives,
which are hidden from ordinary consciousness. To realize one's deep
connection with the events of former lives means at the same time that
one becomes reconciled with one's destiny.
For a fuller coverage of the philosophical riddles like these, the
author must refer to his other works on spiritual science. We can only
mention the more important results of this science but not the
specific ways and means by which it can become convincing.
Philosophy leads by its own paths to the insight that it must pass
from a study of the world to an experience of it, because mere
reflection cannot bring a satisfactory solution to all the riddles of
life. This method of cognition is comparable to the seed of a plant.
The seed can work in a twofold way when it becomes ripe. It can be
used as human food or as seed for a new plant. If it is examined with
respect to its usefulness, it must be looked at in a way different
from the observation that follows the cycle of reproducing a new
plant.
Similarly, man's spiritual experiences can choose either of two roads.
On the one hand, it serves the contemplation of the external world.
Examined from this point of view, one will be inclined to develop a
world conception that asks above all things: How does our knowledge
penetrate to the nature of things? What knowledge can we derive from a
study of the nature of things? To ask these questions is like
investigating the nutritional value of the seed. But it is also
possible to focus attention on the experiences of the soul that are
not diverted by outside impressions, but lead the soul from one level
of being on to another. These experiences are seen as an implanted
driving force in which one recognizes a higher man who uses this life
to prepare for the next. One arrives at the insight that this is the
fundamental impulse of all human soul experience and that knowledge
is related to it as the use of the seed of the plant for food is
comparable to the development of the grain into a new plant. If we
fail to understand this fact, we shall live under the illusion that we
could discover the nature of knowledge by merely observing the soul's
experiences. This procedure is as erroneous as it is to make only a
chemical analysis of the seed with respect to its food value and to
pretend that this represents its real essence. Spiritual science, as
it is meant here, tries to avoid this error by revealing the inner
nature of the soul's experience and by showing that it can also serve
the process of knowledge, although its true nature does not consist in
this contemplative knowledge.
The body-free soul consciousness here described must not
be confused with those enhanced mental conditions that are not
acquired by means of the characterized exercises but result from
states of lower consciousness such as unclear clairvoyance, hypnotism,
etc. In these conditions no body-free consciousness can be attained
but only an abnormal connection between body and soul that differs
from that of the ordinary life. Real spiritual science can be gained
only when the soul finds, in the course of its own disciplined
meditative work, the transition from the ordinary consciousness to one
with which it awakens in and becomes directly aware of the spiritual
world. This inner work consists in a heightening, not a lowering of
the ordinary consciousness.
Through such inner work the human soul can actually attain what
philosophy aims for. The latter should not be underestimated because
it has not attained its objective on the paths that are usually
followed by it. Far more important than the philosophical results are
the forces of the soul that can be developed in the course of
philosophical work. These forces must eventually lead to the point
where it becomes possible to recognize a body-free soul
experience. Philosophers will then recognize that the
world riddles must not merely be considered scientifically
but need to be experienced by the human soul. But the soul must
first attain to the condition in which such an experience is possible.
This brings up an obvious question. Should ordinary knowledge and
scientific knowledge deny its own nature and recognize as a world
conception only what is offered from a realm lying outside its own
domain? As it is, the experiences of the characterized consciousness
are convincing at once also to this ordinary consciousness as long as
the latter does not insist upon locking itself up within its
own walls. The supersensible truths can be found only by a soul
that enters into the supersensible. Once they are found, however, they
can be fully understood by the ordinary consciousness. For they are in
complete and necessary agreement with the knowledge that can be gained
for the world of the senses.
It cannot be denied that, in the course of the history of philosophy,
viewpoints have repeatedly been advanced that are similar to those
described in this final chapter. But in former ages these tendencies
appeared only like byways of the philosophical inquiry. Its
first task was to work its way through everything that could be
regarded as a continuation of the awakening thought experience of the
Greeks. It then could point the way toward supersensible consciousness
on the strength of its own initiative and in awareness of what it can
and what it cannot attain. In former times this consciousness was
accepted, as it were, without philosophical justification. It was not
demanded by philosophy itself. But modern philosophy demands it in
response to what it has achieved already without the assistance
of this consciousness. Without this help it has succeeded in leading
the spiritual investigation into directions that will, if rightly
developed, lead to the recognition of supersensible consciousness.
That is why this final chapter did not start by describing the way in
which the soul speaks of the supersensible when it stands within its
realm. Quite to the contrary, an attempt was made to outline
philosophically the tendencies resulting from the modern world
conceptions, and it was shown how a pursuit of these innate
tendencies leads the soul to the recognition of its own
supersensible nature.
|