II
THE PHILOSOPHICAL BEARING
OF
ANTHROPOSOPHY
No-one, who aims at achieving a radical relation between
his own thought and contemporary philosophical ideas, can avoid the
issue,
raised in the first paragraph of this book, of the existential status
of the
psyche. This he will have to justify not only to himself, but also in
the light
of those ideas. Now many people do not feel this need, since they are
acquainted with the authentically psychic through immediate inner
experience
(Erleben) and know how to distinguish that from the psychic
apprehension
(Erfahren) effected through the senses. It strikes them as an
unnecessary,
perhaps an irritating, intellectual hair-splitting. And if they
are
positively averse, the more philosophically minded are often unwilling
for a
different reason. They are unwilling to concede to inner soul
experiences any
other status than that of subjective apprehensions without cognitive
significance.
They are little disposed therefore to ransack their philosophical
concepts for
those elements in them that could lead on to anthroposophical ideas.
These
repugnances, coming from opposite sides, make the exposition
extraordinarily
difficult. But it is necessary. For in our time the only kind of ideas
to which
cognitive validity can be assigned are such as will bear the same kind
of
critical examination as the laws of natural science must satisfy,
before they
can claim to have been established.
To establish, epistemologically, the validity of anthroposophical
ideas, it is first of all necessary to conceive as precisely as
possible the
manner in which they are experienced. This can be done in several very
different ways. Let us attempt to describe two of them. The first way
requires
that we observe the phenomenon of memory. Rather a weak point
incidentally in
current philosophical theory; for the concepts we find there
concerning memory
throw very little light on it. I take my departure from ideas which I
have, in
point of fact, reached by anthroposophical methods, but which can be
fully
supported both philosophically and physiologically. Limitations of
space will
not permit of my making good this assertion in the present work. I
hope to do
so in a future one.
I am convinced, however, that anyone who succeeds in candidly surveying the
findings
of modern physiological and psychological science will find that they
support
the following observations.
Representations stimulated by sense-impressions enter the
field of unconscious human experience. From there they can be brought
up again,
remembered. Representations themselves are a purely psychic reality;
but
awareness of them in normal waking life is somatically conditioned.
Moreover
the psyche, bound up as it is with the body, cannot by using its own
forces
raise representations from their unconscious to their conscious
condition. For
that it requires the forces of the body. To the end of normal memory
the body
has to function, just as the body has to function in the processes of
its sense-organs,
in order to bring about representations through the senses. If I am to
represent a sensory event, a somatic activity must first come about
within the
sense organs; and, within the psyche, the representation appears as
its result.
In the same way, if I am to remember a representation or idea, an
inner somatic
activity (in refined organs), an activity polarically counter to the
activity
of the senses, must occur; and, as a result, the remembered
representation
comes forth. This representation is related to a sensory event which
was
presented to my soul at some time in the past. I represent that event
to myself
through an inner experience, to which my somatic organisation enables
me.
Keep clearly in mind the character of such a memory-presentation,
and with its help you approach the character of anthroposophical
ideas. They
are certainly not memory-presentations, but they issue in the
psyche in a
similar way. Many people, anxious to form ideas about the spiritual
world in a
less subtle way, find this disappointing. But the spiritual world
cannot be
experienced any more solidly than a happening in the sense world
apprehended in
the past but no longer present to the sight. In the case of memory we
have seen
that our ability to remember such a happening comes from the energy of
the
somatic organisation. To the experience of the existentially psychic,
on the
other hand, as distinct from that of memory, this energy can make no
contribution. Instead, the soul must awaken in itself the ability to
accomplish
with certain representations what the body accomplishes with the
representations of the senses, when it implements their recall. The
former —
elicited from the depths of the psyche solely through the energy of
the psyche,
as memory-presentations are elicited from the depths of human
nature
through its somatic organisation — are representations related to the
spiritual
world. They are available to every soul. What has to be won, in order
to become
aware of them, is the energy to elicit them from the depths of the
psyche by a
purely psychic activity. As the remembered representations of the
senses are
related to a past sense-impression, so are these others related
to a
nexus between the psyche and the domain of spirit, a nexus which is
not via the
sense-world. The human soul stands towards the spiritual world,
as the
whole human being stands towards a forgotten actuality. It comes to
the
knowledge of that world, if it brings, to the point where they awake,
energies
which are similar to those bodily forces that promote memory. Thus,
ideas of
the authentically psychic depend for their philosophical validation on
the kind
of inquiry into the life within us that leads us to find there an
activity
purely psychic, which yet resembles in some ways the activity exerted
in
remembering.
A second way of forming a concept of the purely psychic is as
follows. The attention may be directed to what anthropological
observation has
to say about the willing (operant) human being. An impulse of will
that is to be
carried into effect has as its ground the mental representation of
what is to
be willed. The dependence of this representation on the bodily
organisation
(nervous system) can be physiologically discerned. Bound up with the
representation there is a nuance of feeling, an affective sympathy
with the
represented, which is the reason why this representation furnishes the
impulse
for a willed act. But from that point on psychic experience disappears
into the
depths; and the first thing that reappears in consciousness is the
result. What
is next represented, in fact, is the movement we make in order to
achieve the
represented goal. (Theodor Ziehen puts all this very clearly in his
physiological psychology.) We can now perhaps see how, in the case of
a willed act,
the conscious process of mental representation is suspended in regard
to the
central moment of willing itself. That which is psychically
experienced in the
willing of an operation executed through the body, does not penetrate
normal
consciousness. But we do see plainly enough that that willing is
realised
through an act of the body. What is much harder to see is, that the
psyche,
when it is observing the laws of logic and seeking the truth by
connecting
ideas together, is also unfolding will. A will which is not to be
circumscribed
within physiological laws. For, if that were so, it would be
impossible to
distinguish an illogical — or simply an a-logical — chain of
ideas from
one which follows the laws of logic. (Superficial chatter around the
fancy that
logical consequence could be a property the mind acquires through
adapting
itself to the outer world, need not be taken seriously.) In this
willing, which
takes place entirely within the psyche, and which leads to logically
grounded
convictions, we can detect the permeation of the soul by an entirely
spiritual
activity.
Of what goes on in the will, when it is directed outwards,
ordinary ideation knows as little as a man knows of himself when he is
asleep.
Something similar is true of his being regulated by logic in the
formation of
his convictions; he is less fully conscious of this than he is of the
actual
content of such convictions. Nevertheless anyone capable of looking
inward,
albeit only in the anthropological mode, will be able to form a
concept of the
co-presence of this being-regulated-by logic to
normal
consciousness. He will come to realise that the human being knows of
this being-regulated,
in the manner that he knows while dreaming. It is paradoxical but
perfectly
correct to say: normal consciousness knows the content of its
convictions; but
it only dreams of the regulation by logic that is extant in the
pursuit of
these convictions. Thus we see that, in ordinary-level
consciousness, the
human being sleeps through his willing, when he unfolds and exercises
his will
in an outward direction; he dreams his willing, when, in his thinking,
he is
seeking for convictions. Only it is clear that, in the latter
instance, what he
dreams of cannot be anything corporeal, for otherwise logical and
physiological
laws would coincide. The concept to be grasped is that of the willing
that
lives in the mental pursuit of truth. That is also the concept of an
existentially psychic.
From both of these epistemological approaches, in the sense of
anthroposophy, to the concept of the existentially psychic (and they
are not
the only possible ones), it becomes evident how sharply this concept
is
divorced from visions, hallucinations, mediumship or any kind of
abnormal
psychic activity. For the origin of all these abnormalities must be
sought in
the physiologically determinable. But the psychic, as anthroposophy
understands
it, is not only something that is experienced in the mode of normal
and healthy
consciousness; it is something that is experienced, even while
representations
are being formed, in total vigilance — and is experienced in the same
way that
we remember a happening undergone earlier in life, or alternatively in
the same
way that we experience the logically conditioned formation of our
convictions.
It will be seen that the cognitive experience of anthroposophy
proceeds by way
of representations and ideas that maintain the character of that
normal
consciousness with which, as well as with reality, the external world
endows
us; while at the same time they add to it endowments leading into the
domain of
the spirit. By contrast the visionary, hallucinatory, etc. type of
experience
subsists in a consciousness that adds nothing to the norm, but
actually takes
away from it by eliminating some faculties already acquired; so that
there the
level of consciousness falls below the level that obtains in conscious
sense-perception.
For those of my readers who are acquainted with what I have
written elsewhere
concerning recollection and memory I would add the following. Representations
that have
entered the unconscious and are subsequently remembered are to be
located, so
long as they remain unconscious, as representations within that
component of
the human body which is there identified as a life-body (etheric
body).
But the activity, through which representations anchored in the
life-body
are remembered, belongs to the physical body. I emphasise this in case
some,
who jump hastily to conclusions, should construe as an inconsistency
what is in
fact a distinction made necessary by this particular context.