III
CONCERNING THE LIMITS OF
KNOWLEDGE
The inner nature of man demands that he experience his relation
with ultimate reality. Among thinkers who pursue this goal with
untiring energy
we find a large number discoursing on certain “boundaries” of
knowledge. And,
if we listen attentively, we cannot help noticing how collision with
these
boundaries, when it is experienced by a candid mind, tends in the
direction of
an inner psychic apprehension, a “purely noetic experience” such as
was
indicated in the first paragraph of this book. Consider how the
profoundly able
mind of Friedrich Theodor Vischer, in the packed essay he wrote on
Johannes
Volkelt’s book Dream-Phantasy (Traumphantasie), reports its own
reaction
to one such limit of cognition:
“No mind where no nerve-centre, where no brain”, say our
opponents. No nerve-centre, we say, no brain unless it had been
first
prepared for by innumerable stages from below upwards. It is easy to
babble,
with a sneer, about Mind careering through granite and chalk — just as
easy as
it is for us to ask, with a sneer, how the albumen in the brain flies
up aloft
into ideas. Human knowledge is extinguished at any attempt to span the
distance
from one step to the other.
It will remain a secret how it comes about that nature — beneath
which spirit must somehow or other be slumbering — presents itself as
such a
backlash of spirit that we bruise ourselves on it. The diremption
appears so
absolute that Hegel’s formulation of it as “Being other” and “Being
outside
itself”, brilliant as it is, says almost nothing; it simply drapes the
abruptness of the party wall. We may look to Fichte for a really
adequate
acknowledgment of the abruption and of the shock of the backlash, but
we still
find no explanation of it. (Compare F. T. Vischer: “Old and New”
(Altes und
Neues), 1881, Part I, p. 229 f.)
Vischer lays his finger on the kind of issue with which
anthroposophy too engages. But he fails to realise that, precisely at
such a
frontier of knowledge as this, another mode of knowledge can begin. He
desires
to go on living on these frontiers with the same brand of cognition
that
sufficed until he reached them. Anthroposophy seeks to demonstrate
that the
possibility of systematic knowledge (science) does not cease at the
point where
ordinary cognition “bruises” itself, at the point where this
“abruption” and
these “shocks” from the backlash make themselves felt; but that, on
the
contrary, the experiences that ensue from them lead naturally towards
the
development of another type of cognition, which transforms the
backlash into
perception of spirit — a perception which at the outset, in its
initial stage,
may be compared with tactile perception in the realm of the
senses.
In Part III of Altes und Neues Vischer says: “Very well: there is
no soul alongside of the body (he means, for the materialists); what
we call
matter simply becomes soul at the highest level of organisation known
to us, in
the brain, and soul evolves to mind or spirit. In other words, we are
to be
satisfied with a half-baked concept, which for the divisive
understanding
is a simple contradiction.” Anthroposophy echoes and supplements this
with:
Very well: for the divisive understanding there is a contradiction.
But for the
soul, the contradiction becomes the point of departure of a knowledge
before
which the divisive understanding is pulled up short, because it
encounters the
backlash of actual spirit.
Again, Gideon Spicker, the author of a series of discerning
publications, who also wrote Philosophical Confession of a Former
Capuchin
(Philosophische Bekenntnis eines ehemaligen Kapuziners, 1910)
identifies
incisively enough one of the confining limits of ordinary
cognition:
Whatever philosophy a man confesses, whether it is dogmatic or
sceptical, empirical or transcendental, critical or eclectic, every
one,
without exception, starts from an unproven and unprovable premise,
namely the
necessity of thinking. No investigation ever gets behind this
necessity,
however deep it may dig. It has to be simply, and groundlessly,
accepted; every
attempt to prove its validity already presupposes it. Beneath it yawns
a
bottomless abyss, a ghastly darkness, illuminated by no ray of light.
We know
not whence that necessity comes, nor whither it leads. As to whether a
gracious
God or whether an evil demon implanted it in the reason, we are
equally
uncertain. (p. 30.)
Reflection on the nature of thought, then, leads of itself to one
of the frontiers of normal cognition. Anthroposophy occupies this
frontier; it
knows how necessity confronts and blocks discursive thought like an
impenetrable wall. But when the act of thinking is experienced as
such, the
wall becomes penetrable. This experienced thinking finds a light of
contemplation wherewith to illuminate the “darkness illuminated by no
ray of
light” of merely discursive thought. It is only for the dominion of
the senses
that the abyss is bottomless; if we do not halt before it, but make up
our
minds to risk going ahead with thought, beyond the point at which it
has to
jettison all that the senses have furnished to it, then in that
“bottomless
abyss” we find the realities of the spirit …*”
One could continue almost indefinitely exemplifying the reaction
of serious minds before the “frontiers of knowledge”. And it would
serve to
show that anthroposophy has its proper place as the inevitable product
of
mental evolution in the modern age. There are plenty of prophetic
signs, if we
know how to read them.