I COULD not at that time bring myself to reflections concerning public
life in Austria which might have taken a deeper hold in any way
whatever upon my mind. I merely continued to observe the
extraordinarily complicated relationships involved. Expressions which
won my deeper interest I could find only in connection with Karl
Julius Schröer. I had the pleasure of being with him often just at
this time. His own fate was closely bound up with that of German
Austria-Hungary. He was the son of Tobias Schröer, who conducted a
German school in Presburg and wrote dramas as well as books on
historical and aesthetic subjects. The last appeared under the name
Christian Oeser, and they were favourite text-books. The poetic
writings of Tobias Gottfried Schröer, although they are doubtless
significant and received marked recognition within restricted circles,
did not become widely known. The sentiment that breathes through them
was opposed to the dominant political current in Hungary. They had to
be published in part without the author's name in German regions
outside of Hungary. Had the tendencies of the author's mind been known
in Hungary, he would have risked, not only dismissal from his post,
but also severe punishment.
Karl Julius Schröer thus experienced the impulse toward Germanism even
as a young man in his own home. Under this impulse he developed his
intimate devotion to the German nature and German literature as well
as a great devotion to everything belonging to Goethe or concerning
him. The history of German poetry by Gervinus had a profound influence
upon him. He went in the fortieth year of the nineteenth century to
Germany to pursue his studies in the German language and literature at
the universities of Leipzig, Halle, and Berlin. After his return he
was occupied in teaching German literature in his father's school, and
in conducting a Seminar. He now became acquainted with the Christmas
folk-plays which were enacted every year by the German colonists in
the region of Presburg. There he was face to face with Germanism in a
form profoundly congenial to him. The roving Germans who had come from
the west into Hungary hundreds of years before had brought with them
these plays of the old home, and continued to perform them as they had
done at the Christmas festival in regions which no doubt lay in the
neighbourhood of the Rhine. The Paradise story, the birth of Christ,
the coming of the three kings were alive in popular form in these
plays. Schröer then published them, as he heard them, or as he read
them in old manuscripts that he was able to see at peasants' homes,
using the title
Deutsche Weinachtspiele aus Ungarn.(1)
The delightful experience of living in the German folk life took an
even stronger hold upon Schröer's mind. He made journeys in order to
study German dialects in the most widely separated parts of Austria.
Wherever the German folk was scattered in the Slavic, Magyar, or
Italian geographical regions, he wished to learn their individuality.
Thus came into being his glossary and grammar of the Zipser dialect,
which was native to the south of the Carpathians; of the Gottschze
dialect, which survived with a little fragment of German folk in
Krain; the language of the Heanzen, which was spoken in western
Hungary.
For Schröer these studies were never merely a scientific task. He
lived with his whole soul in the revelation of the folk-life, and
wished by word and writing to bring its nature to the consciousness of
those men who have been uprooted from it by life. He was then a
professor in Budapest. There he could not feel at home in the presence
of the prevailing current of thought; so he removed to Vienna, where
at first he was entrusted with the direction of the evangelical
schools, and where he later became a professor of the German language
and literature. When he already occupied this position, I had the
privilege of knowing him and of becoming intimate with him. At the
time when this occurred, his whole sentiment and life were directed
toward Goethe. He was engaged in editing the second part of
Faust, and writing an introduction for this, and had already
published the first part.
When I went to call at Schröer's little library, which was also his
work-room, I felt that I was in a spiritual atmosphere in the highest
degree beneficial to my mental life. I understood at once why Schröer
was maligned by those who accepted the prevailing literary-historical
methods on account of his writings, and especially on account of his
Geschicte der Deutschen Dichtung im neunzehnten Jahrhundert.(2)
He did not write at all like the
members of the Scherer school, who treated literary phenomena after
the fashion of investigators in natural science. He had certain
sentiments and ideas concerning literary phenomena, and he spoke these
out in frank, manly fashion without turning his eyes much at the
moment of writing to the sources. It had even been said
that he had written his exposition from the wrist out.
This interested me very little. I experienced a spiritual warmth when
I was with him. I could sit by his side for hours. Out of his inspired
heart the Christmas plays lived on his lips, the spirit of the German
dialect, the course of the life of literature. The relation between
dialect and cultured speech became perceptible to me in a practical
way. I experienced a real joy when he spoke to me, as he had already
done in his lectures, of the poet of the Lower Austrian dialect,
Joseph Misson, who wrote the splendid poem,
Da Naaz, a niederösterreichischer Bauernbua, geht ind Fremd.(3)
Schröer then constantly gave me books from his library in which I
could pursue further what was the content of this conversation. I
always had, in truth, when I sat there alone with Schröer, the feeling
that still another was present Goethe's spirit. For Schröer lived so
strongly in the spirit and the work of Goethe that in every sentiment
or idea which entered his soul he feelingly asked the question,
Would Goethe have felt or thought thus?
I listened in a spiritual sense with the greatest possible sympathy to
everything that came from Schröer. Yet I could not do otherwise even
in his presence than build up independently in my own mind that toward
which I was striving in my innermost spirit. Schröer was an idealist,
and the world of ideas as such was for him that which worked as a
propulsive force in the creation of nature and of man. I then found it
indeed difficult to express in words for myself the difference between
Schröer's way of thinking and mine. He spoke of ideas as the
propelling forces in history. He felt life in the idea itself. For me
the life of the spirit was behind the ideas, and these were only the
phenomena of that life in the human soul. I could then find no other
terms for my way of thinking than objective idealism. I
wished thereby to denote that for me the reality is not in the idea;
that the idea appears in man as the subject, but that just as colour
appears on a physical object, so the idea appears on the spiritual
object, and that the human mind the subject perceives it there as
the eye perceives colour on a living being.
My conception, however, Schröer very largely satisfied in the form of
expression he used when we talked about that which reveals itself as
folk-soul. He spoke of this as of a real spiritual being
which lives in the group of individual men who belong to a folk. In
this matter his words took on a character which did not pertain merely
to the designation of an idea abstractly held. And thus we both
observed the texture of ancient Austria and the individualities of the
several folk-souls active in Austria. From this side it was possible
for me to conceive thoughts concerning the state of public life which
penetrated more deeply into my mind.
Thus my experience at that time was strongly bound up with my
relationship to Karl Julius Schröer. What, however, were more remote
from him, and in which I strove most of all for an inner explanation,
were the natural sciences. I wished to know that my objective
idealism was in harmony with the knowledge of nature.
It was during the period of my most earnest intercourse with Schröer
that the question of the relation between the spiritual and natural
worlds came before my mind in a new form. This happened at first quite
independently of Goethe's way of thought concerning the natural
sciences. For even Schröer could tell me nothing distinctive
concerning this realm of Goethe's creative work. He was happy whenever
he found in one or another natural scientist a generous recognition of
Goethe's observations concerning the beings of plants and animals. As
regards Goethe's theory of colour, however, he was met on all sides by
natural scientific conceptions utterly opposed. So in this direction
he developed no special opinion.
My relationship to natural science was not at this time of my life
influenced from this side, in spite of the fact that in my intercourse
with Schröer I came into close touch with Goethe's spiritual life. It
was determined much more by the difficulties I experienced when I had
to think out the facts of optics in the sense of the physicist.
I found that light and sound were thought of in an analogy which is
invalid. The expressions sound in general and light
in general were used. The analogy lay in the following: The
individual tones and sounds were viewed as specially modified
air-vibrations; and objective sound, outside of the human perception,
was viewed as a state of vibration of the air. Light was thought of
similarly. That which occurs outside of man when he has a perception
by means of phenomena caused by light was defined as vibration in
ether. The colours, then, are especially formed ether-vibrations.
These analogies became at that time an actual torment to my inner
life. For I believed myself perfectly clear in the perception that the
concept sound is merely an abstract union of the
individual occurrences in the sphere of sound; whereas
light signifies a concrete thing over against the
phenomena in the sphere of illumination. Sound was for me
a composite abstract concept; light a concrete reality. I
said to myself that light is really not perceived by the senses;
colours are perceived by means of light, which manifests
itself everywhere in the perception of colours but is not itself
sensibly perceived. White light is not light, but that
also is a colour. Thus for me light became a reality in the
sense-world, yet in itself not perceptible to the senses. Now there
came before my mind the conflict between nominalism and realism as
this was developed within scholasticism. The realists maintained that
concepts were realities which lived in things and were simply
reproduced out of these by human understanding. The nominalists
maintained, on the contrary, that concepts were merely names formed by
man which include together a complex of what is in the things, but
names which have no existence themselves. It now seemed to me that the
sound experience must be viewed in the nominalist manner and the
experiences which proceed from light in the realist manner.
I carried this orientation into the optics of the physicist. I had to
reject much in this science. Then I arrived at perceptions which gave
me a way to Goethe's colour theory.
On this side the door opened before me through which to approach
Goethe's writings on natural science. I first took to Schröer brief
treatises I had written on the basis of my views in the field of
natural science. He could make but little of them; for they were not
yet worked out on the basis of Goethe's way of thinking, but I had
merely attached at the end this remark: When men come to the
point of thinking about nature as I have here set forth, then only
will Goethe's researches in science be confirmed. Schröer felt
an inner pleasure when I made such a statement, but beyond this
nothing then came of the matter. The situation in which I then found
myself comes out in the following: Schröer related to me one day that
he had spoken with a colleague who was a physicist. But, said the man,
Goethe opposed himself to Newton, and Newton was such a
genius; to which Schröer replied: But Goethe also was a
genius. Thus again I felt that I had a riddle to solve with
which I struggled entirely alone.
In the views at which I had arrived in the physics of optics there
seemed to me to be a bridge between what is revealed to insight into
the spiritual world and that which comes out of researches in the
natural sciences. I felt then a need to prove to sense experience, by
means of certain experiments in optics in a form of my own, the
thoughts which I had formed concerning the nature of light and that of
colour.
It was not easy for me to buy the things needed for such experiments;
for the means of living I derived from tutoring was little enough.
Whatever was in any way possible for me I did in order to arrive at
such plans of experimentation in the theory of light as would lead to
an unprejudiced insight into the facts of nature in this field.
With the physicist's usual arrangements for experiments I was familiar
through my work in Reitlinger's physics laboratory. The mathematical
treatment of optics was easy to me, for I had already pursued thorough
courses in this field. In spite of all objections raised by the
physicists against Goethe's theory of colour, I was driven by my own
experiments farther and farther away from the customary attitude of
the physicist toward Goethe. I became aware that all such
experimentation is only the establishing of certain facts about
light to use an expression of Goethe's and not
experimentation with light itself. I said to myself: The colours
are not, in Newton's way of thinking, produced out of light; they come
to manifestation when obstructions hinder the free unfolding of the
light. It seemed to me that this was the lesson to be learned
directly from my experiments. Through this, however, light was for me
removed from the properly physical realities. It took its place as a
midway stage between the realities perceptible to the senses and those
visible to the spirit.
I was not inclined forthwith to engage in a merely philosophical
course of thinking about these things. But I held strongly to this: to
read the facts of nature aright. And then it became constantly clearer
to me how light itself does not enter the realm of the
sense-perceptible, but remains on the farther side of this, while
colours appear when the sense perceptible is brought into the realm of
light. I now felt myself compelled anew to press inward to the
understanding of nature from the most diverse directions. I was led
again to the study of anatomy and physiology. I observed the members
of the human, animal, and plant organisms in their formations. In this
study I came in my own way to Goethe's theory of metamorphosis. I
became more and more aware how that conception of nature which is
attainable through the senses penetrates through to that which was
visible to me in spiritual fashion.
If in this spiritual way I directed my look to the soul-activity of
man, thinking, feeling, and willing, then the spiritual
man took form for me, a clearly visible image. I could not
linger in the abstractions in which men generally think when they
speak of thinking, feeling, and willing. In these living
manifestations I saw creative forces which set the man as
spirit there before me. If I then turned my glance to the
sense-manifestation of man, this became complete to my observation by
means of the spirit-form which ruled in the sense-perceptible.
I came upon the sensible-supersensible form of which Goethe speaks and
which thrusts itself, both for the true natural vision and for the
spiritual vision, between what the senses grasp and what the spirit
perceives.
Anatomy and physiology struggled through step by step to the
sensible-supersensible form. And in this struggling I through my look
fell, at first in a very imperfect way, upon the threefold
organization of the human being, concerning which after having
pursued my studies regarding this for thirty years in silence I
first began to speak openly in my book
Von Seelenrätzeln.(4)
It then became clear to me that in
that portion of the human organization in which the shaping is chiefly
directed to the elements of the nerves and the senses, the
sensible-supersensible form also stamps itself most strongly in the
sense-perceptible. The head organization appeared to me as that in
which the sensible-supersensible becomes most strongly visible in the
sensible form. On the other hand, I was forced to look upon the
organization consisting of the limbs as that in which the
sensible-supersensible most completely submerges itself, so that in
this organization the forces active in nature external to man pursue
their work in the shaping of the human body. Between these poles of
the human organization everything seemed to me to exist which
expresses itself in a rhythmic manner, the processes of breathing,
circulation, and the like. At that time I found no one to whom I could
have spoken of these perceptions. If I referred here or there to
something of this, then it was looked upon at once as the result of a
philosophic idea, whereas I was certain that I had disclosed these
things to myself by means of an understanding drawn from unbiased
anatomical and physiological experimentation.
For the mood which depressed my soul by reason of this isolation in my
perceptions I found an inner release only when I read over and over
the conversation which Goethe had with Schiller as the two went away
from a meeting of the Society for Scientific Research in Jena. They
were both agreed in the view that nature should not be observed in
such piece-meal fashion as had been done in the paper of the botanist
Batsch which they had heard read. And Goethe with a few strokes drew
before Schiller's eyes his archetypal plant. This through
a sensible-supersensible form represents the plant as a whole out of
which leaf, blossom, etc., reproducing the whole in detail, shape
themselves. Schiller, because he had not yet overcome his Kantian
point of view, could see in this whole only an
idea which human understanding formed through observation
of the details. Goethe would not allow this to pass. He saw
spiritually the whole as he saw with his senses the group of details,
and he admitted no difference in principle between the spiritual and
the sensible perception, but only a transition from the one to the
other. To him it was clear that both had the right to a place in the
reality of experience. Schiller, however, did not cease to maintain
that the archetypal plant was no experience, but an idea. Then Goethe
replied, in his way of thinking, that in this case he perceived his
ideas with his eyes. There was for me a rest after a long struggle in
my mind, in that which came to me out of the understanding of these
words of Goethe, to which I believed I had penetrated Goethe's
perception of nature revealed itself before my mind as a spiritual
perception.
Now, by reason of an inner necessity, I had to strive to work in
detail through all of Goethe's scientific writings. At first I did not
think of undertaking an interpretation of these writings, such as I
soon afterward published in an introduction to them in Kürschner's
Deutsche National Literatur. I thought much more of setting
forth independently some field or other of natural science in the way
in which this science now hovered before me as spiritual.
My external life was at that time not so ordered that I could
accomplish this. I had to do tutoring in the most diverse subjects.
The pedagogical situations through which I had to find my
way were complex enough. For example, there appeared in Vienna a
Prussian officer who for some reason or other had been forced to leave
the German military service. He wished to prepare himself to enter the
Austrian army as an officer of engineers. Through a peculiar course of
fate I became his teacher in mathematics and physical-scientific
subjects. I found in this teaching the deepest satisfaction; for my
scholar was an extraordinarily lovable man who formed a
human relationship with me when we had put behind us the mathematical
and scientific developments he needed for his preparation. In other
cases also, as in those of students who had completed their work and
who were preparing for doctoral examinations, I had to give the
instruction, especially in mathematics and the physical sciences.
Because of this necessity of working again and again through the
physical sciences of that time, I had ample opportunity of immersing
myself in the contemporary views in these fields. In teaching I could
give out only these views; what was most important to me in relation
to the knowledge of nature I had still to carry locked up within
myself.
My activity as a tutor, which afforded me at that time the sole means
of a livelihood, preserved me from one-sidedness. I had to learn many
things from the foundation up in order to be able to teach them. Thus
I found my way into the mysteries of book-keeping, for I
found opportunity to give instruction even in this subject.
Moreover, in the matter of pedagogical thought, there came to me from
Schröer the most fruitful stimulus. He had worked for years as
director of the Evangelical schools in Vienna, and he had set forth
his experiences in the charming little book,
Unterrichtsfrage.(5)
What I read in this could then
be discussed with him. In regard to education and instruction, he
spoke often against the mere imparting of information, and in favour
of the evolution of the full and entire human being.
- German Christmas Plays from Hungary.
- History of German Poetry in the Nineteenth Century.
- Ignatius, a peasant boy of Lower Austria, goes abroad.
- Riddles of the Soul.
- Questions on Teaching.
|