Lecture IV
Theosophy and Darwin
Berlin
27th October, 1904
We find two important cultural
currents in the present. The one shows itself in Darwin (Charles D.
1809–1882 English naturalist and writer), which has already peaked,
the other in Tolstoy, which is in its beginning.
Numerous of our contemporaries
who occupy themselves with the questions which deal with the name Darwin
are probably of the opinion that Darwinism signifies a sort of final
truth; that on the other hand everything that the human beings thought
once is overcome, and that at the same time this finally found truth
is something that is valid up to the most distant future. Many people
cannot imagine that the opinions of the human beings are something absolutely
changeable. They have no idea of the fact that the most important concept
which we find just in Darwinism, the concept of evolution, is applicable
not less to the spiritual life than to the natural life, and that human
opinions and human knowledge are subjected to evolution above all. Not
before you want to take an overview of a bigger time of evolution of
the human spirit, it becomes clear to you that truth, knowledge and
views of a certain epoch developed out of the former points of view,
have changed and that they change in future again.
Theosophy would fulfil its
task little unless it applied this concept of evolution to the great
phenomena of life, of the spiritual life above all. That is why we do
not consider the narrow ken of a present human being but from a higher
point of view what is connected with the name Darwin. Besides, we have
to go somewhat far back in time, because nobody can understand those
phenomena if he puts them only before himself if he does not consider
them in connection with other, similar phenomena. Theosophy enables
us to consider these phenomena in the corresponding broad context. Theosophy
looks at the development of the human mind in the different forms of
existence, as we have got to know them in the last talks. This human
mind, this human being, as he is today and as he is since millennia,
is nothing ready, nothing finished. He will no longer be the same as
today in millennia and in even more distant times. In order to understand
how he places himself in the world today and looks at his task in the
world at first, we have to emphasise the typical peculiarities of the
present human being. However, to be able to do this, we have to extend
our view so that we do not overestimate certain concepts, certain ideas
which we have.
It is in particular a concept
which the human being today overestimates too much: this is the concept
of conscious human activity, as well as today we understand our consciousness.
Whenever the human being considers art, technology and the like which
comes from him, then he has the concept of conscious activity, of conscious
thinking in certain way in the background.
He does not notice at all
that there are round him in the world activities of art and technical
activities which are at least as significant as the human activities,
however, differ from them by the fact that the human being carries out
his activities consciously; since the human being is intellectually
active in the world. In the end, everything that the human being undertakes
is a realised human thought. The house lives first in the mind of the
architect, and if it is ready, it is a materialised idea. But we also
find such materialised thoughts, otherwise, in the world. Look only
once impartially not through the glasses of the present world view at
the regular movement of the stars, and you find that a universal thought
forms the basis of the universe like a house is based on an idea.
How should the human being
be able as astronomer to force this construction of the universe in
mathematical and other laws, how should he be able to find the laws
of the universe if these laws were not included in this universe itself
first? Or take to resume another example the dens which an animal, the
beaver, carries out. They are so artistic, of such a mathematical regularity
that the engineer, who studies these matters, must say to himself: if
he had the task to build the most suitable under the given circumstances,
he could carry out nothing more suitable, nothing more perfect according
to the gradient of the river and the requirements of the beaver's mode
of life. Thus you can pursue the whole nature if you pursue it only
impartially, and you see everywhere that what the human being consciously
accomplishes in thoughts, transforms into reality is around us and is
infiltrated with thoughts.
We are used to call an instinctive
activity what the animal accomplishes. We would also call the artistic
den of a beaver, the ant heap, and the beehive instinctive activities.
However, thus we get around to understanding that the human activity
only thereby differs from this activity round us that the human being
knows about the laws of his activity that he has a knowledge of it.
We just call that an instinctive activity which is performed by a being
that is not aware of the laws according to which it works. If you look
at two beings much differing in their development like the human being
in his conscious activity and, for example, the beaver or the ant this
way, you notice the big difference between the human conscious mental
activity and the unaware, instinctive activity of a relatively imperfect
animal. Between these both activities there are innumerable many degrees.
We can also describe those which the human being has gone through in
a long, but compared with the aeon, short prehistory. We are led in
the course of these talks today I can only indicate it to former levels
of human cultural activity, to the human ancestors in a bygone time,
to the so-called Atlanteans whose culture declined long ago and whose
descendants are the cultural creators of our present human race. If
we pursue the mental activity, the whole way of human activity in the
environment with these Atlanteans, who were our predecessors before
many millennia, and see with which means the theosophical world view
gets to know the mental activity of these ancestors, then we would realise
that it does not stand back so far from our present mental activity
like the activity of the animals that, however, our Atlantean ancestors
were substantially different from our contemporaries. These Atlantean
ancestors were absolutely able to erect big buildings, absolutely able
to control nature; but their activity was more instinctive than the
completely conscious activity of the present humanity. It was not as
instinctive as that of the animals, but more instinctive than that of
the present humanity.
The history of the ancient
Babylon and Assyria tells about skilfully erected buildings, and our
architects who study them assure us that they were created so extraordinarily
that the conscious activity of modern architects is not yet so far to
accomplish what in those days the human being was able to accomplish
on relatively unaware levels. You must not take offence to the word
“instinctive.” It is only a small difference between the
mind of the modern human being and that of the former one. If we traced
back the activities, which in order to express myself a little bit popularly
people perform more mechanically, more in a feeling way, more intuitively
than consciously, then we would come to our Atlantean ancestors who
worked much more instinctively than the human beings of historic times.
Thus we can say that we can pursue the human mental activity historically
up to a time in which the mental activity did not yet exist to the present-day
degree, even did not exist in the beginning of the Atlantean age. We
have also to admit on the other side that the human being develops in
the future again to quite different mental abilities than his mind has
today. So, our present-day reason which is the typical of the present
human being is not something that is everlasting or even is invariable,
but it is something that is developing. It originated and develops to
other, higher forms.
In what does the activity
of this mind consist? We have already indicated this. It consists in
the fact that the human being more and more overcomes the merely instinctive
of his activity and clearly knows about the laws which he applies in
the outer life, clearly also knows about the laws which have come into
being in nature. If, however, this mind itself is developing, it has
gone through apparently different levels of development; it is advanced
from relatively imperfect levels to a higher level in the present, and
it still ascends to others. If we look back to the Atlantean ancestors,
we see the mind arising first in its daybreak, and then it develops
up to a culmination to be replaced in future by a higher mental activity.
This mind cannot develop at one go. It must realise, so to speak, gradually
what is its task. From stage to stage it must walk if it wants to know
about the laws which are in our nature and which it itself realises.
This can only happen successively. What should this mind do? It should
understand the things round itself, know about them. It has to recreate
them in his inside, has to recreate as concepts what is outside in reality.
It has to gain this knowledge bit by bit. However, this knowledge must
correspond to the outer things. But the outer things are manifold. The
things which we can pursue in the world are spirit, soul and external
physical reality.
Reason did not come into
being in the soul in one go to understand this external nature in her
whole variety. The human being had to acquire the different kinds of
reality gradually, the spiritual, the psychic and the physical. It is
very interesting to pursue how it acquires them. The human being is
not able to understand the things outside in the world, before he has
not acquired them in the loneliness of his reflection. The human being
would never be able to understand an ellipse as an orbit of a planet
unless he had acquired the laws of the ellipse, the forms of it in loneliness
before.
After he has found the concept
in himself, he sees it realised also in the outside world. Not until
the human being has created the knowledge in him, he can find it in
the outside world materialised. We have to get clear about the fact
that this has happened on the most different levels of the development
of reason during the evolution of our human race. The human reason had
at first to make a concept of the picture he can see in the outside
world to itself to understand it. As a rule, the human being recognises
his inner life first. This is the mind, the soul. Only bit by bit he
gets to the concepts of his surroundings. You can observe this with
every child. It does not have a concept of the lifeless nature at first
but that of the soul. It hits the table against which it has stumbled
because it regards it as of the same kind. It is also in the cultural
development that way. We have to observe an epoch of the cultural development
which the researchers have called animism. In the whole nature the human
being saw animated beings, in every stone, in every rock, in every spring
he saw something living because he himself was alive and can form the
concept of life from his inside. Thus the former human races also have
the concept of the mind at first, then that of soul and life, and last
of all they acquired the concept of the external mechanical, lifeless.
If we look back in historic
times, at the time of ancient India with its Vedas and the Vedic philosophy,
and study these ancient world views, we find that the human beings had
a concept of the spiritual in the most comprehensive sense. The concept
of the spirit lives in these old, marvellous documents. However, the
ancient peoples were not able to understand the individual spirit, the
special mind. They had a great idea of the all-embracing world spirit
and its different transformations in the world, but they were not yet
able to look into the individual human soul, to grasp the spirit of
the human soul. They had no concept of psychology in our sense, of that
which one calls spiritual science or humanities which will only be a
real spiritual science once. They thought the spirit, but did not understand
the individual mind. If we pursue the rudiments of cultural development
up to the beginning of Hellenism, we find that in that time even those
who call themselves philosophers apply the concept of the soul to the
whole world. Everything is ensouled with them. If they have to understand
the individual soul, their understanding fails.
At first the human being
forms the general concept of the spirit and the general concept of the
soul. But only later he approaches these concepts mentally to understand
them in the single being. In the whole Middle Ages we can pursue that
the human being does not yet penetrate into the individual mind. I would
like to mention Giordano Bruno (1548–1600) here only. Who studies the
philosophy of this predominant spirit finds that he has an all-embracing
concept of a world life, a concept of life in its highest significance.
The whole world is life to him, in every stone, in every star he sees
life. Every single part of the universe is to him a member, an organ
of the universe. He looks up to the stars as enlivened beings. He also
considers the individual human being strictly in this sense. In the
living human being he sees only a stage of the general psychic human
life. He calls the human being, who stands physically before us, spirit
spread out in space, life spread out in space. He understands death
as nothing else than contracting life in one single point. Expansion
and contraction are the phenomena of life and death for him. Life is
eternal. That life which appears to us in the physical is life spread
out in space, life that does not appear in the physical is contracted
life. Thus life changes perpetually extending and contracting. Except
these both qualities of Giordano Bruno's comprehensive concept
of life I may still quote the concept of the sky, a concept which science
has not got by a long stretch which one would have to study, in which
one would have to become engrossed to return to the comprehensive idea
of the sky. However, also Giordano Bruno was not yet able to understand
the individual living being, the special being.
However, the possibility
to understand these individual living beings develops just in this time.
There one only starts understanding the processes in the human body;
there one starts understanding how the blood flows in the body how the
activities of the body take place. What we call physiology today started
taking shape at that time. If you look at the naturalists of the past,
like Paracelsus (1493–1541), then you see that these have no concept;
at that time the human cultural development had not yet created the
concept which has the mastery over our world view: the concept of mechanism.
The concept of mechanism was grasped at last. The human being understood
at last what a machine is. Not until after Giordano Bruno and Paracelsus
the scientific thinking starts developing the concept of the machine,
the concept of the mechanical.
We have seen how in the
course of time the development of human mind has successively grasped
the concepts: spirit, soul, life, and mechanism. Now the reverse follows
in our development. After the human evolution had grasped the concepts,
it applied them to the outer things, and the first epoch is in this
regard the application of the concept of the machine to the surrounding
reality. One wants to understand not only the machine, but one applies
the concept of the machine also to the single being. The application
of the concept of mechanism is the characteristic of the epoch of which
only few centuries have elapsed. The 17th century belongs to this epoch.
If we go back to it, we find the philosopher Descartes (René
D., 1596–1650). He applies the concept of mechanism to the animal world.
He does not differentiate between the animal and lifeless things, but
he considers the animals and plants as beings which are on par with
automata, as beings completely merging in purely mechanical activity.
For humanity had advanced so far that it could grasp the concept of
mechanism and apply it to nature but could not apply the concept of
soul and spirit to the individual being. Thus the human being saw as
it were through the plant, animal and human souls. There he could grasp
nothing; he was not able to consider the plant, the animal and the human
being as something higher. Indeed, the external shape of any being is
mechanical. Any being on the physical plane is mechanical. Reason conceives
this lowest level first. It understands the physical body of the different
world things, and it understands it quite naturally as a purely physical,
mechanical activity at first. This was the epoch of the mechanical understanding
of the world and the epoch of the non-cognition of any higher reality
of the world at the same time. This epoch extends till our time. We
see how today the human being tries hard to apply the concept of the
mechanical to the outside world; we see how Descartes understands plant,
animal and human being mechanically, because the physical human body
is also mechanical. Hence, also the assertion that the human being is
only a machine.
Then the great discoverers
and the big technical activity of the mechanical world, the industry,
come. We see reason and the mechanical concept celebrating their biggest
triumphs. It penetrates up to the single living beings, and it understands
them in their physical-technical interrelation. While in the 18th century
one could not yet understand the living together of the animals and
plants mechanically, the 19th century was able to do this. Development
is not the essential part, but that a relationship exists between the
beings. Evolution is not the typical of Darwinism; for a theory of evolution
existed always. You can go back to Aristotle, to the Vedic philosophy,
also with Goethe, you find everywhere that a theory of evolution existed
at all times. Also in the modern scientific sense there is already in
the beginning of the 19th century a theory of evolution, the Lamarckism.
Lamarck's theory considers the animal world in such a way that
it ascends from the imperfect to the perfect up to the physical human
being. But in those days Lamarckism could not yet become popular. Lamarck
was not understood. Only the middle of 19th century was mature to understand
the theory of evolution mechanically. The experience of the external
physical life had advanced so far that this marvellous building could
be collated which Darwin has put up. Darwin did nothing else than to
put up and grasp in thoughts mechanically what surrounds us.
The next was that the human
being grasped the idea of the physical relationship of the material
human being with the other material organisms. This was the last, the
keystone in the building. We get to know the significance of the keystone
if we speak about the philosophy of Ernst Haeckel.
If we apply the concept
of development to the human beings themselves, we find that it is comprehensible
that a level of development of the spiritual human being must be the
conquest of the spiritual thought. Darwinism has occupied this field
by means of purely external causes, by the law of the struggle for existence.
Hence, it signifies a necessary developmental phase of the human culture,
and we understand from the necessity of its origin the necessity of
its overcoming. Thereby we extend our look understanding Darwinism as
a phase of the scientific development. Only prejudiced people argue
that Darwinism considers the world, the facts as they are real. One
knows the facts; they were there always; only the way of thinking is
different. If you read Goethe's essays Story of My Botanical
Studies, you find almost literally what Darwin describes in his
way. Also in Goethe's Metamorphosis of Plants you find
a lot. Goethe supports a by far higher, much more comprehensive theory
of life on the same facts. It is a theory from which modern science
will get something higher than Darwinism is. This is the Goethean theory
of the interrelation of the organisms. But like any phase of development
must be gone through, the study of Darwinism also had to be gone through.
The whole situation in the middle of the 19th century enabled humanity
to become ripe to introduce mechanical thoughts into the animal and
plant realms. This powerful thought has expressed itself in the mechanical
struggle for existence of the living beings. It has its origin in a
particular kind of the human life itself.
Beside his observations,
Darwin referred everything that was of importance for his theory to
the doctrine of Malthus. It is this doctrine of the growth of population
and food which induced him to establish the external struggle for existence
as the principle of perfection. Malthus represents the principle that
humanity reproduces faster than the supply of food. The availability
of food increases slowly in arithmetic progression, like 1 - 2 - 3 -
4 - and so on, the population grows exponentially, like 1 - 2 - 4 -
8 - 1 6 - and so on. If this is the case, it is natural that with the
unequal growth of food in proportion to the growth of population a struggle
for existence originates. This is the hopeless so-called Malthusian
principle. Whereas Malthus only wanted to draw logical conclusions from
this principle in the first half of the 19th century which meant the
way of living together, a possibility to further civilisation, to improve
the conditions of human life, Darwin said to himself: if this principle
holds sway in human life, it is the more sure that the struggle for
existence is everywhere. Hence, concerning Darwinism you recognise the
clearest that the human being starts from himself. He transfers what
he observes in himself to the external nature. The purely mechanical
principle of the war of all against all which has become the principle
of the way of life in the 19th century faces us in Darwin's theory
again. I do not want to speak of the fact that the scientific investigations
do no longer allow us to adhere to the principle of the struggle for
existence, but I want only to emphasise that the application of the
principle is not necessary.
However, we have also to
understand that anything comprehensive, anything ultimate was not given
with the fact that the human being understands the whole environment
mechanically. In the beings something else than the mere mechanism exists.
We have seen that the mechanism, the external physical guise, is only
one part, only one of the elements of which the world is composed. Because
we understand the external appearance we even understand the lowest
part of the beings existing around us. Any phase of the human cultural
development also has its negative aspect; any phase shows its extremes.
Somebody who would have seen clearly in the time of the blossoming Darwinism
would have said to himself: indeed, the development of the mechanical
thought must happen; but this thought is not yet suitable to understand
life, soul, and mind in the special being. First we must learn to apply
Bruno's ideas of the all-embracing world life to the individual
special being which stands before us then we are able to gradually understand
the world round ourselves in transparency up to the spirit. Today we
can only apply the concept of the mechanical to the single beings. In
future one must succeed in finding the concepts of life, soul and mind
again in the single beings. We must become able to look at the plant
not only with the eyes of the mechanically thinking physiologist, but
with the eyes of the scientist rising to higher stages of life. We must
ascend to the concepts of soul and spirit. These concepts were already
grasped in preceding epochs; modern humanity has to learn to apply them.
This would have been the idea of anybody who surveys the matters completely.
Still another idea, another
cause was obstructive there. This was to consider oneself satisfied
with the mechanical concepts of the world and to believe that with it,
with the mechanical point of view, everything is achieved that the mechanism
explains everything. These spirits existed also. This was in the time
when one defined the purely material the be-all and end-all, the time
of Büchner (Ludwig B., 1824–1899, materialistic philosopher), Vogt
(Karl V., 1817–1895, materialistic philosopher) and also concerning
his concepts, not his research Haeckel. This is the other extreme. In
between were the careful spirits who could not rise to a higher understanding
of the world matters, who had, however, a dark feeling that they had
only understood a part, own a part only. These are the careful researchers
who understood the right thing; they said to themselves that they are
on a level where they could not yet investigate everything, and who
revered what they could not investigate as the unfathomable in humility.
For those researchers the feeling had to join that behind that which
they found something unknown is hidden toward which they do not have
a vocation to intervene with their mechanical thinking.
Now we want to ask once
which researchers have thought in such a way, and there we meet one
who belongs to this epoch who writes: “I take the view that all
organic beings which have lived on this earth are descendant of a prototype
which was animated by the creator.” This is a careful researcher,
a researcher who understands the external world mechanically, but cannot
get to the recognition of life and spirit; he keeps to the idea of a
creator and reveres him in humility. The same researcher may also be
quoted against the radicals who appeared in the wake of Darwinism. One
also wanted to explain the language mechanically.
What this researcher spoke
out of his feeling is the point of view which the theosophist must take
up toward the Darwinist theory of evolution. He shows us a great overview
of the evolution of our race; he shows us that Darwinism is only a phase
which leads to the concept of life, to the application of the concept
of soul and spirit. As we have a mechanical science today, we have a
science of life, a soul science and spiritual science in future. This
is the viewpoint of theosophy; and it wants nothing else than to anticipate
what the future has to bring to humanity. It wants to point whereto
we go, and one has to emphasise that this theosophical view just agrees
with the careful researchers who have found the right viewpoint by themselves.
For these words did not come from an obscure Darwinist who could not
get rid of his traditional prejudices who wanted to connect religious
prejudices with Darwinism, but from one whose competence you do not
doubt: they issue from Charles Darwin himself!
|