LECTURE TWO
THE STUDY of Spiritual Science should always go hand in hand with
practical experience of how the mind works. It is impossible to get
entirely clear about many things that we discussed in the last
lecture unless one tries to get a kind of living grasp of what
thinking involves in terms of actualities. For why is it that among
the very persons whose profession it is to think about such
questions, confusion reigns, for example, as to the relation
between the general concept of the “triangle-in-general”
and specific concepts of individual triangles? How is it that people
puzzle for centuries over questions such as that of the hundred
possible and the hundred real thalers cited by Kant? Why is it that
people fail to pursue the very simple reflections that are necessary
to see that there cannot really be any such thing as a “pragmatic”
account of history, according to which the course of events always
follows directly from preceding events? Why do people not reflect in
such a way that they would be repelled by this impossible mode of
regarding the history of man, so widely current nowadays? What is the
cause of all these things?
The reason is that far too little trouble is taken over learning to
handle with precision the activities of thinking, even by people
whose business this should be. Nowadays everyone wants to feel that
he has a perfect claim to say: “Think? Well, one can obviously
do that.” So they begin to think. Thus we have various
conceptions of the world; there have been many philosophers —
a great many. We find that one philosopher is after this and another
is after that, and that many fairly clever people have drawn
attention to many things. If someone comes upon contradictions in
these findings, he does not ponder over them, but he is quite pleased
with himself, fancying that now he can “think” indeed. He
can think again what those other fellows have thought out, and feels
quite sure that he will find the right answer himself. For no one
nowadays must make any concession to authority! That would deny the
dignity of human nature! Everyone must think for himself. That is the
prevailing notion in the realm of thought.
I do not know if people have reflected that this is not their
attitude in other realms of life. No one feels committed to belief in
authority or to a craving for authority when he has his coat made at
the tailor's or his shoes at the shoemaker's. He does not say: “It
would be beneath the dignity of man to let one's things be made by
persons who are known to be thoroughly acquainted with their
business.” He may perhaps even allow that it is necessary to
learn these skills. But in practical life, with regard to thinking,
it is not agreed that one must get one's conceptions of the world
from quarters where thinking and much else has been learnt. Only
rarely would this be conceded to-day.
This is one tendency that dominates our life in the widest circles,
and is the immediate reason why human thinking is not a very
widespread product nowadays. I believe this can be quite easily
grasped. For let us suppose that one day everybody were to say:
“What! — learn to make boots? For a long time that has
been unworthy of man; we can all make boots.” I don't know if
only good boots would come from it. At all events, with regard to the
coining of correct thoughts in their conception of the world, it is
from this sort of reasoning that men mostly take their start at the
present day. This is what gives its deeper meaning to my remark of
yesterday — that although thought is something a man is
completely within, so that he can contemplate it in its inner being,
actual thinking is not as common as one might suppose. Besides this,
there is to-day a quite special pretension which could gradually
go so far as to throw a veil over all clear thinking. We must pay
attention to this also; at least we must glance at it.
Let us suppose the following. There was once in Görlitz a
shoemaker named Jacob Boehme. He had learnt his craft well —
how soles are cut, how the shoe is formed over the last, and how the
nails are driven into the soles and leather. He knew all this down to
the ground. Now supposing that this shoemaker, by name Jacob Boehme,
had gone around and said: “I will now see how the world is
constructed. I will suppose that there is a great last at the
foundation of the world. Over this last the world-leather was once
stretched; then the world-nails were added, and by means of them the
world-sole was fastened to the world-upper. Then boot-blacking was
brought into play, and the whole world-shoe was polished. In this way
I can quite clearly explain to myself how in the morning it is
bright, for then the shoe-polish of the world is shining, but in the
evening it is soiled with all sorts of things; it shines no longer.
Hence I imagine that every night someone has the duty of repolishing
the world-boot. And thus arises the difference between day and
night.” Let us suppose that Jacob Boehme had said this.
Yes, you laugh, for of course Jacob Boehme did not say this; but
still he made good shoes for the people of Görlitz, and for that
he employed his knowledge of shoe-making. But he also developed his
grand thoughts, through which he wanted to build up a conception
of the world; and for that he resorted to something else. He said to
himself: My shoe-making is not enough for that; I dare not apply to
the structure of the world the thoughts I put into making shoes. And
in due course he arrived at his sublime thoughts about the world.
Thus there was no such Jacob Boehme as the hypothetical figure I
first sketched, but there was another one who knew how to set about
things. But the hypothetical “Jacob Boehmes”, like the
one you laughed over — they exist everywhere to-day.
For example, we find among them physicists and chemists who have
learnt the laws governing the combination and separation of
substances; there are zoologists who have learnt how one examines and
describes animals; there are doctors who have learnt how to treat the
physical human body, and what they themselves call the soul. What do
they all do? They say: When a person wants to work out for himself a
conception of the world, then he takes the laws that are learnt in
chemistry, in physics, or in physiology — no others are
admissible — and out of these he builds a conception of the
world for himself. These people proceed exactly as the hypothetical
shoemaker would have done if he had constructed the world-boot, only
they do not notice that their world-conceptions come into existence
by the very same method that produced the hypothetical world-boot. It
does certainly seem rather grotesque if one imagines that the
difference between day and night comes about through the soiling of
shoe-leather and the repolishing of it in the night. But in terms of
true logic it is in principle just the same if an attempt is made to
build a world out of the laws of chemistry, physics, biology and
physiology. Exactly the same principle! It is an immense presumption
on the part of the physicist, the chemist, the physiologist, or the
biologist, who do not wish to be anything else than physicist,
chemist, physiologist, biologist, and yet want to have an opinion
about the whole world. The point is that one should go to the root of
things and not shirk the task of illuminating anything that is not so
clear by tracing it back to its true place in the scheme of things.
If you look at all this with method and logic, you will not need to
be astonished that so many present-day conceptions of the world yield
nothing but the “world-boot”. And this is something that
can point us to the study of Spiritual Science and to the pursuit of
practical trains of thought; something that can urge us to examine
the question of how we must think in order to see where shortcomings
exist in the world.
There is something else I should like to mention in order to show
where lies the root of countless misunderstandings with regard to the
ideas people have about the world. When one concerns oneself with
world-conceptions, does one not have over and over again the
experience that someone thinks this and someone else that; one man
upholds a certain view with many good reasons (one can find good
reasons for everything), while another has equally good reasons for
his view; the first man contradicts his opponent with just as
good reasons as those with which the opponent contradicts him. Sects
arise in the world not, in the first place, because one person or
another is convinced about the right path by what is taught here or
there. Only look at the paths which the disciples of great men have
had to follow in order to come to this or that great man, and then
you will see that herein lies something important for us with regard
to karma. But if we examine the outlooks that exist in the world
to-day, we must say that whether someone is a follower of Bergson, or
of Haeckel, or of this or that (karma, as I have already said, does
not recognise the current world-conception) depends on other things
than on deep conviction. There is contention on all sides!
Yesterday I said that once there were Nominalists, persons who
maintained that general concepts had no reality, but were merely
names. These Nominalists had opponents who were called Realists (the
word had a different meaning then). The Realists maintained that
general concepts are not mere words, but refer to quite definite
realities. In the Middle Ages the question of Realism versus
Nominalism was always a burning one, especially for theology, a
sphere of thought with which present-day thinkers trouble themselves
very little. For in the time when the question of Nominalism versus
Realism arose (from the eleventh to the thirteenth centuries) there
was something that belonged to the most important confessions of
faith, the question about the three “Divine Persons” —
Father, Son and Holy Ghost — who form One Divine Being, but are
still Three real Persons. The Nominalists maintained that these three
Divine Persons existed only individually, the “Father”
for Himself, the “Son” for Himself, and the “Holy
Ghost” for Himself; and if one spoke of a “Collective
God” Who comprised these Three, that was only a name for the
Three. Thus Nominalism did away with the unity of the Trinity. In
opposition to the Realists, the Nominalists not only explained away
the unity, but even regarded it as heretical to declare, as the
Realists did, that the Three Persons formed not merely an imaginary
unity, but an actual one.
Thus Nominalism and Realism were opposites. And anyone who goes
deeply into the literature of Realism and Nominalism during these
centuries gets a deep insight into what human acumen can produce. For
the most ingenious grounds were brought forward for Nominalism, just
as much as for Realism. In those days it was more difficult to be
reckoned as a thinker because there was no printing press, and it was
not an easy thing to take part in such controversies as that between
Nominalism and Realism. Anyone who ventured into this field had to be
better prepared, according to the ideas of those times, than is
required of people who engage in controversies nowadays. An immense
amount of penetration was necessary in order to plead the cause of
Realism, and it was equally so with Nominalism. How does this
come about? It is grievous that things are so, and if one reflects
more deeply on it, one is led to say: What use is it that you are so
clever? You can be clever and plead the cause of Nominalism, and you
can be just as clever and contradict Nominalism. One can get quite
confused about the whole question of intelligence! It is distressing
even to listen to what such characterisations are supposed to mean.
Now, as a contrast to what we have been saying, we will bring forward
something that is perhaps not nearly so discerning as much that has
been advanced with regard to Nominalism or to Realism, but it has
perhaps one merit — it goes straight to the point and indicates
the direction in which one needs to think.
Let us imagine the way in which one forms general concepts; the way
in which one synthesizes a mass of details. We can do this in two
ways: first as a man does in the course of his life through the
world. He sees numerous examples of a certain kind of animal: they
are silky or woolly, are of various colours, have whiskers, at
certain times they go through movements that recall human “washing”,
they eat mice, etc. One can call such creatures “cats”.
Then one has formed a general concept. All these creatures have
something to do with what we call “cats”. But now let us
suppose that someone has had a long life, in the course of which he
has encountered many cat-owners, men and women, and he has noticed
that a great many of these people call their pets “Pussy”.
Hence he classes all these creatures under the name of “Pussy”.
Hence we now have the general concept “Cats” and the
general concept “Pussy”, and a large number of individual
creatures belonging in both cases to the general concept. And yet no
one will maintain that the general concept “Pussy” has
the same significance as the general concept “Cats”. Here
the real difference comes out. In forming the general concept “Pussy”
which is only a summary of names that must rank as individual names,
we have taken the line, and rightly so, of Nominalism; and in forming
the general concept “Cats” we have taken the line of
Realism, and rightly so. In one case Nominalism is correct; in the
other. Realism. Both are right. One must only apply these methods
within their proper limits. And when both are right, it is not
surprising that good reasons for both can be adduced. In taking the
name “Pussy”, I have employed a somewhat grotesque
example. But I can show you a much more significant example and I
will do so at once.
Within the scope of our objective experience there is a whole realm
where Nominalism — the idea that the collective term is only a
name — is fully justified. We have “one”, “two”,
“three”, “four”, “five”, and so
on, but it is impossible to find in the expression “number”
anything that has a real existence. “Number” has no
existence. “One”, “two”, “three”,
“five”, “six”, — they exist. But what I
said in the last lecture, that in order to find the general concept
one must let that which corresponds to it pass over into movement —
this cannot be done with the concept “Number”. One “one”
does not pass over into “two”. It must always be taken as
“one”. Not even in thought can we pass over into two, or
from two into three. Only the individual numbers exist, not “number”
in general. As applied to the nature of numbers, Nominalism is
entirely correct; but when we come to the single animal in relation
to its genus, Realism is entirely correct. For it is impossible for a
deer to exist, and another deer, and yet another, without there being
the genus “deer”. The figure “two” can exist
for itself, “one”, “seven”, etc., can exist
for themselves. But in so far as anything real appears in number, the
number is a quality, and the concept “number” has no
specific existence. External things are related to general concepts
in two different ways: Nominalism is appropriate in one case, and
Realism in the other.
On these lines, if we simply give our thoughts the right direction,
we begin to understand why there are so many disputes about
conceptions of the world. People generally are not inclined, when
they have grasped one standpoint, to grasp another as well. When in
some realm of thought somebody has got hold of the idea “general
concepts have no existence”, he proceeds to extend to it the
whole make-up of the world. This sentence, “general concepts
have no existence” is not false, for when applied to the
particular realm which the person in question has considered, it is
correct. It is only the universalising of it that is wrong. Thus it
is essential, if one wants to form a correct idea of what thinking
is, to understand clearly that the truth of a thought in the realm to
which it belongs is no evidence for its general validity. Someone can
offer me a perfectly correct proof of this or that and yet it will
not hold good in a sphere to which it does not belong. Anyone,
therefore, who intends to occupy himself seriously with the paths
that lead to a conception of the world must recognise that the first
essential is to avoid one-sidedness. That is what I specially want to
bring out to-day. Now let us take a general look at some matters
which will be explained in detail later on.
There are people so constituted that it is not possible for them to
find the way to the Sprit, and to give them any proof of the Spirit
will always be hard. They stick to something they know about, in
accordance with their nature. Let us say they stick at something that
makes the crudest kind of impression on them — Materialism.
We need not regard as foolish the arguments they advance as a defence
or proof of Materialism, for an immense amount of ingenious writing
has been devoted to the subject, and it holds good in the first place
for material life, for the material world and its laws.
Again, there are people who, owing to a certain inwardness, are
naturally predisposed to see in all that is material only the
revelation of the spiritual. Naturally, they know as well as the
materialists do that, externally, the material world exists; but
matter, they say, is only the revelation, the manifestation, of the
underlying spiritual. Such persons may take no particular interest in
the material world and its laws. As all their ideas of the spiritual
come to them through their own inner activity, they may go through
the world with the consciousness that the true, the lofty, in which
one ought to interest oneself — all genuine reality — is
found only in the Spirit; that matter is only illusion, only external
phantasmagoria. This would be an extreme standpoint, but it can
occur, and can lead to a complete denial of material life. We should
have to say of such persons that they certainly do recognize what is
most real, the Spirit, but they are one-sided; they deny the
significance of the material world and its laws. Much acute thinking
can be enlisted in support of the conception of the universe held by
these persons. Let us call their conception of the universe:
Spiritism. Can we say that the Spiritists are right? As
regards the Spirit, their contentions could bring to light some
exceptionally correct ideas, but concerning matter and its laws they
might reveal very little of any significance. Can one say the
Materialists are correct in what they maintain? Yes, concerning
matter and its laws they may be able to discover some exceptionally
useful and valuable facts; but in speaking of the Spirit they may
utter nothing but foolishness. Hence we must say that both parties
are correct in their respective spheres.
There can also be persons who say: “Yes, but as to whether in
truth the world contains only matter, or only spirit, I have no
special knowledge; the powers of human cognition cannot cope with
that. One thing is clear — there is a world spread out around
us. Whether it is based upon what chemists and physicists, if they
are materialists, call atoms, I know not. But I recognize the
external world; that is something I see and can think about. I have
no particular reason for supposing that it is or is not spiritual at
root. I restrict myself to what I see around me.” From the
explanations already given we can call such Realists, and their
concept of the universe: Realism. Just as one can enlist
endless ingenuity on behalf of Materialism or of Spiritism, and just
as one can be clever about Spiritism and yet say the most foolish
things on material matters, and vice versa, so one can advance the
most ingenious reasons for Realism, which differs from both Spiritism
and Materialism in the way I have just described.
Again, there may be other persons who speak as follows. Around us are
matter and the world of material phenomena. But this world of
material phenomena is in itself devoid of meaning. It has no real
meaning unless there is within it a progressive tendency; unless from
this external world something can emerge towards which the human soul
can direct itself, independently of the world. According to this
outlook, there must be a realm of ideas and ideals within the
world-process. Such people are not Realists, although they pay
external life its due; their view is that life has meaning only if
ideas work through it and give it purpose. It was under the influence
of such a mood as this that Fichte once said: Our world is the
sensualised material of our duty.
[ Note 2 ]
The adherents of such a
world-outlook as this, which takes everything as a vehicle for the
ideas that permeate the world-process, may be called Idealists and
their outlook: Idealism. Beautiful and grand and glorious
things have been brought forward on behalf of this Idealism. And in
this realm that I have just described — where the point is to
show that the world would be purposeless and meaningless if ideas
were only human inventions and were not rooted in the world-process —
in this realm Idealism is fully justified. But by means of it one
cannot, for example, explain external reality. Hence one can
distinguish this Idealism from other world-outlooks:
We now have side by side four justifiable world-outlooks, each with
significance for its particular domain. Between Materialism and
Idealism there is a certain transition. The crudest kind of
materialism — one can observe it specially well in our day,
although it is already on the wane — will consist in this, that
people carry to an extreme the saying of Kant — Kant did not do
this himself! — that in the individual sciences there is only so much
real science as there is mathematics. This means that from being a
materialist one can become a ready-reckoner of the universe, taking
nothing as valid except a world composed of material atoms. They
collide and gyrate, and then one calculates how they inter-gyrate. By
this means one obtains very fine results, which show that this way of
looking at things is fully justified. Thus you can get the
vibration-rates for blue, red, etc.; you take the whole world as a
kind of mechanical apparatus, and can reckon it up accurately. But
one can become rather confused in this field. One can say to oneself:
“Yes, but however complicated the machine may be, one can never
get out of it anything like the perception of blue, red, etc. Thus if
the brain is only a complicated machine, it can never give rise to
what we know as soul-experiences.” But then one can say, as
du Bois-Reymond once said: If we want to explain the world in strictly
mathematical terms, we shall not be able to explain the simplest
perception, but if we go outside a mathematical explanation, we shall
be unscientific. The most uncompromising materialist would say, “No,
I do not even calculate, for that would presuppose a superstition —
it would imply that I assume that things are ordered by measure and
number.” And anyone who raises himself above this crude
materialism will become a mathematical thinker, and will recognize as
valid only whatever can be treated mathematically. From this results
a conception of the universe that really admits nothing beyond
mathematical formulae. This may be called Mathematism.
Someone, however, might think this over, and after becoming a
Mathematist he might say to himself: “It cannot be a
superstition that the colour blue has so and so many vibrations. The
world is ordered mathematically. If mathematical ideas are found to
be real in the world, why should not other ideas have equal reality?”
Such a person accepts this — that ideas are active in the
world. But he grants validity only to those ideas that he discovers
outside himself — not to any ideas that he might grasp from his
inner self by some sort of intuition or inspiration, but only to
those he reads from external things that are real to the senses. Such
a person becomes a Rationalist, and his outlook on the world is that
of Rationalism. If, in addition to the ideas that are found in
this way, someone grants validity also to those gained from the moral
and the intellectual realms, then he is already an Idealist. Thus a
path leads from crude Materialism, by way of Mathematism and
Rationalism, to Idealism.
But now Idealism can be enhanced. In our age there are some men who
are trying to do this. They find ideas at work in the world, and this
implies that there must also be in the world some sort of beings in
whom the ideas can live. Ideas cannot live just as they are in any
external object, nor can they hang as it were in the air. In the
nineteenth century the belief existed that ideas rule history. But
this was a confusion, for ideas as such have no power to work. Hence
one cannot speak of ideas in history. Anyone who understands that
ideas, if they are there are all, are bound up with some being
capable of having ideas, will no longer be a mere Idealist; he
will move on to the supposition that ideas are connected with beings.
He becomes a Psychist and his world-outlook is that Psychism.
The Psychist, who in his turn can uphold his outlook with an immense
amount of ingenuity, reaches it only through a kind of one-sidedness,
of which he can eventually become aware.
Here I must add that there are adherents of all the world-outlooks
above the horizontal stroke; for the most part they are stubborn fold
who, owing to some fundamental element in themselves, take this or
that world-outlook and abide by it, going no further. All the beliefs
listed below the line have adherents who are more easily accessible
to the knowledge that individual world-outlooks each have one special
standpoint only, and they more easily reach the point where they pass
from one world-outlook to another.
When someone is a Psychist, and able as a thinking person to
contemplate the world clearly, then he comes to the point of saying
to himself that he must presuppose something actively psychic in the
outside world. But directly he not only thinks, but feels sympathy
for what is active and willing in man, then he says to himself: “It
is not enough that there are beings who have ideas; these beings must
also be active, they must be able also to do things.” But this
is inconceivable unless these beings are individual beings. That is,
a person of this type rises from accepting the ensoulment of the
world to accepting the Spirit or the Spirits of the world. He is not
yet clear whether he should accept one or a number of Spirits, but he
advances from Psychism to Pneumatism to a doctrine of the
Spirit.
If he has become in truth a Pneumatist, then he may well grasp what I
have said in this lecture about number — that with regard to
figures it is somewhat doubtful to speak of a “unity”.
Then he comes to the point of saying to himself: It must therefore be
a confusion to talk of one undivided Spirit, of one undivided Pneuma.
And he gradually becomes able to form for himself an idea of the
Spirits of the different Hierarchies. Then he becomes in the true
sense a Spiritist, so that on this side there is a direct transition
from Pneumatism to Spiritism.
These world-outlooks are all justified in their own field. For there
are fields where Psychism acts illuminatingly, and others where
Pneumatism does the same. Certainly, anyone who wishes to deliberate
about an explanation of the universe as thoroughly as we have tried
to do must come to Spiritism, to the acceptance of the Spirits of the
Hierarchies. For to stop short at Pneumatism would in this case mean
the following. If we are Spiritists, then it may happen that people
will say to us: “Why so many spirits? Why bring numbers into
it? Let there be One Undivided Spirit!” Anyone who goes more
deeply into the matter knows that this objection is like saying: “You
tell me there are two hundred midges over there. I don't see
two hundred; I see only a single swarm.” Exactly so would an
adherent of Pneumatism stand with regard to a Spiritist. The
Spiritist sees the universe filled with the Spirits of the
Hierarchies; the Pneumatist sees only the one “swarm” —
only the Universal Spirit. But that comes from an inexact view.
Now there is still another possibility: someone may not take the path
we have tried to follow to the activities of the spiritual
Hierarchies, but may still come to an acceptance of certain spiritual
beings. The celebrated German philosopher, Leibnitz, was a man of
this kind. Leibnitz had got beyond the prejudice that anything merely
material can exist in the world. He found the actual, he sought the
actual. (I have treated this more precisely in my book,
Riddles of Philosophy.)
His view was that a being — as, for
example, the human soul — can build up existence in itself. But
he formed no further ideas on the subject. He only said to himself
that there is such a being that can build up existence in itself, and
force concepts outwards from within itself. For Leibnitz, this being
is a “Monad”. And he said to himself: “There must
be many Monads, and Monads of the most varied capabilities. If I had
here a bell, there would be many monads in it — as in a swarm
of midges — but they would be monads that had never come even
so far as to have sleep-consciousness, monads that are almost
unconscious, but which nevertheless develop the dimmest of concepts
within themselves. There are monads that dream; there are monads that
develop waking ideas within themselves; in short, there are monads of
the most varied grades.”
A person with this outlook does not come so far as to picture to
himself the individual spiritual beings in concrete terms, as the
Spiritist does, but he reflects in the world upon the spiritual
element in the world, allowing it to remain indefinite. He calls it
“Monad” — that is, he conceives of it only as
though one were to say: “Yes, there is spirit in the world and
there are spirits, but I describe them only by saying, ‘They
are entities having varying powers of perception.’ I pick out
from them an abstract characteristic. So I form for myself this
one-sided world-outlook, on behalf of which as much as can be said
has been said by the highly intelligent Leibnitz. In this way I
develop Monadism.” Monadism is an abstract Spiritism.
But there can be persons who do not rise to the level of the Monads;
they cannot concede that existence is made up of being with the most
varied conceptual powers, but at the same time they are not content
to allow reality only to external phenomena; they hold that “forces”
are dominant everywhere. If, for example, a stone falls to the
ground, they say, “That is gravitation!” When a magnet
attracts bits of iron, they say: “That is magnetic force!”
They are not content with saying simply, “There is the magnet,”
but they say, “The magnet presupposes that supersensibly,
invisibly, a magnetic force is present, extending in all directions.”
A world-outlook of this kind — which looks everywhere for
forces behind phenomena — can be called Dynamism.
Then one may say: “No, to believe in ‘forces’ is
superstition” — an example of this is Fritz Mauthner's
Critique of Language, where you find a detailed argument to
this effect. It amounts to taking your stand on the reality of the
things around us. Thus by the path of Spiritism we come through
Monadism and Dynamism to Realism again.
But now one can do something else still. One can say: “Certainly
I believe in the world that is spread out around me, but I do not
maintain any right to claim that this world is the real one. I can
say of it only that it ‘appears’ to me. I have no right
to say more about it.” There you have again a difference. One
can say of the world that is spread out around us. “This is the
real world,” but one can also say, “I am clear that there
is a world which appears to me; I cannot speak of anything more. I am
not saying that this world of colours and sounds, which arises only
because certain processes in my eyes present themselves to me as
colours, while processes in my ears present themselves to me as
sounds — I am not saying that this world is the true world. It
is a world of phenomena.” This is the outlook called
Phenomenalism.
We can go further, and can say: “The world of phenomena we
certainly have around us, but all that we believe we have in these
phenomena is what we have ourselves added to them, what we have
thought into them. Our own sense-impressions are all we can rightly
accept. Anyone who says this — mark it well! — is not an
adherent of Phenomenalism. He peels off from the phenomena everything
which he thinks comes only from the understanding and the reason, and
he allows validity only to sense-impressions, regarding them as some
kind of message from reality.” This outlook may be called
Sensationalism.
A critic of this outlook can then say: “You may reflect as much
as you like on what the senses tell us and bring forward ever so
ingenious reasons for your view — and ingenious reasons can be
given — I take my stand on the point that nothing real exists
except that which manifests itself through sense-impressions; this I
accept as something material.”
This is rather like an atomist saying: “I hold that only atoms
exist, and that however small they are, they have the attributes
which we recognize in the physical world” — anyone who says this
is a materialist. Thus, by another path, we arrive back at
Materialism.
All these conceptions of the world that I have described and written
down for you really exist, and they can be maintained. And it is
possible to bring forward the most ingenious reasons for each of
them; it is possible to adopt any one of them and with ingenious
reasons to refute the others. In between these conceptions of the
world one can think out yet others, but they differ only in degree
from the leading types I have described, and can be traced back to
them. If one wishes to learn about the web and woof of the world,
then one must know that the way to it is through these twelve points
of entry. There is not merely one conception of the world that can be
defended, or justified, but there are twelve. And one must admit that
just as many good reasons can be adduced for each and all of them as
for any particular one. The world cannot be rightly considered from
the one-sided standpoint of one single conception, one single mode of
thought; the world discloses itself only to someone who knows that
one must look at it from all sides. Just as the sun — if we go
by the Copernican conception of the universe — passes through
the signs of the Zodiac in order to illuminate the earth from twelve
different points, so we must not adopt one standpoint, the standpoint
of Idealism, or Sensationalism, or Phenomenalism, or any other
conception of the world with a name of this kind; we must be in a
position to go all round the world and accustom ourselves to the
twelve different standpoints from which it can be contemplated. In
terms of thought, all twelve standpoints are fully justifiable. For a
thinker who can penetrate into the nature of thought, there is not
one single conception of the world, but twelve that can be equally
justified — so far justified as to permit of equally good
reasons being thought out for each of them. There are twelve such
justified conceptions of the world.
Tomorrow we will start from the points of view we have gained in this
way, so that from the consideration of man in terms of thought we may
rise to a consideration of the cosmic.
|