Lecture IV
Dornach,
December 27, 1922
In the
last lecture, I spoke of a former view of life from which the modern
scientific view has evolved. It still combined the qualitative with
the form-related or geometrical elements of mathematics, the
qualitative with the quantitative. One can therefore look back at a
world conception in which the triangle or another geometrical form
was an inner experience no matter whether the form referred to the
surface of a given body or to its path of movement. Geometrical and
arithmetical forms were intensely qualitative inner experiences. For
example, a triangle and a square were each conceived as emerging from
a specific inward experience.
This conception could change into a different one only when men lost
their awareness that everything quantitative — including
mathematics — is originally experienced by man in direct
connection with the universe. It changed when the point was reached
where the quantitative was severed from what man experiences. We can
determine this moment of separation precisely. It occurred when all
concepts of space that included man himself were replaced by the
schematic view of space that is customary today, according to which,
from an arbitrary starting point, the three coordinates are drawn.
The kind of mathematics prevalent today, by means of which man wants
to dominate the so-called phenomena of nature, arose in this form
only after it had been separated from the human element. Expressing
it more graphically, I would say in a former age man perceived
mathematics as something that he experienced within himself together
with his god or gods, whereby the god ordered the world. It came as
no surprise therefore to discover this mathematical order in the
world. In contrast to this, to impose an arbitrary space outline or
some other mathematical formula on natural phenomena — even if
such abstract mathematical concepts can be identified with
significant aspects in these so-called natural phenomena — is a
procedure that cannot be firmly related to human experiences. Hence,
it cannot be really understood and is at most simply assumed to be a
fact. Therefore in reality it cannot be an object of any perception.
The most that can be said of such an imposition of mathematics on
natural phenomena is that what has first been mathematically thought
out is then found to fit the phenomena of nature. But why this is so
can no longer be discovered within this particular world
perception.
Think back to the other worldview that I have previously described to
you, when all corporeality was regarded as image of the spirit. One
looking at a body found in it the image of spirit. One then looked
back on oneself, on what — in union with one's own divine
nature — one experienced as mathematics through one's own
bodily constitution. As a work of art is not something obscure but is
recognized as the image of the artist's ideas, so one found in
corporeal nature the mathematical images of what one had experienced
with one's own divine nature. The bodies of external nature
were images of the divine spiritual. The instant that mathematics is
separated from man and is regarded only as an attribute of bodies
that are no longer seen as a reflection of spirit, in that instant
agnosticism creeps into knowledge.
Take a concrete example, the first phenomenon that confronts us after
the birth of scientific thinking, the Copernican system. It is not my
intention today or in any of these lectures to defend either the
Ptolemaic or the Copernican system. I am not advocating either one. I
am only speaking of the historical fact that the Copernican system
has replaced the Ptolemaic. What I say today does not imply that I
favor the old Ptolemaic system over the Copernican. But this must be
said as a matter of history. Imagine yourself back in the age when
man experienced his own orientation in space: above-below,
right-left, front-back. He could experience this only in connection
with the earth. He could, for example, experience the vertical
orientation in himself only in relation to the direction of gravity.
He experienced the other two in connection with the four compass
points according to which the earth itself is oriented. All this he
experienced together with the earth as he felt himself
standing firmly on it. He thought of himself not just as a being that
begins with the head and ends a the sole of the feet. Rather, he felt
himself penetrated by the force of gravity, which had something to do
with his being but did not cease at the soles of his feet. Hence,
feeling himself within the nature of the gravitational force, man
felt himself one with the earth. For his concrete experience, the
starting point of his cosmology was thus given by the earth.
Therefore he felt he Ptolemaic system to be justified.
Only when man severed himself from mathematics, only then was it
possible also to sever mathematics from the earth and to found an
astronomical system with its center in the sun. Man had to lose the
old experience-within-himself before he could accept a system with
its center outside the earth. The rise of the Copernican system is
therefore intimately bound up with the transformation of civilized
mankind's soul mood. The origin of modern scientific thinking
cannot be separated from the general mental and soul condition, but
must be viewed in context with it.
It is only natural that statements like this are considered absurd by
our contemporaries, who believe in the present world view far more
fervently than the sectarians of olden days believed in their dogmas.
But to give the scientific mode of thinking its proper value, it must
be seen as arising inevitably out of human nature and evolution. In
the course of these lectures, we shall see that by doing this we are
actually assigning far greater value to science than do the modern
agnostics.
Thus the Copernican world conception came into being, the projection
of the cosmic center from the earth to the sun. Fundamentally, the
whole cosmic thought edifice of Giordano Bruno,
[ 32 ]
who was born in 1548 and burned at the stake in Rome in 1600, was already
contained in the Copernican world view. It is often said that Giordano Bruno
glorifies the modern view of nature, glorifies Copernicanism. One must have
deep insight into the inner necessity with which this new cosmology
arose if one is to have any feeling at all for the manner and tone in
which Giordano Bruno speaks and writes. Then one sees that Giordano
Bruno does not sound like the followers of the new view or like the
stragglers of the old view. He really does not speak about the cosmos
mathematically so much as lyrically. There is something musical in
the way Giordano Bruno describes the modern conception of nature. Why
is that? The reason is that Giordano Bruno, though he was rooted with
his whole soul in a bygone world perception, told himself with his
outward intellect: The way things have turned out in history, we
cannot but accept the Copernican world picture. He understood the
absolute necessity that had been brought about by evolution. This
Copernican world view, however, was not something he had worked out
for himself. It was something given to him, and which he found
appropriate for his contemporaries. Belonging as he did to an older
world conception, he could not help but experience inwardly what he
had to perceive and accept as knowledge. He still had the faculty of
inner experience, but he did not have scientific forms for it.
Therefore although he described them so wonderfully, he did not
follow the Copernican directions of thought in the manner of
Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler, or Newton.
[ 33 ]
Instead, he tried to
experience the cosmos in the old way, the way that was suitable when
the world cosmos was experienced within one's being. But in
order to do this, mathematics would have had to be also mysticism,
inward experience, in the way I described yesterday. This it could
not be for Giordano Bruno. The time for it was past. Hence, his
attempt to enter the new cosmology through living experience became
an experience, not of knowledge but of poetry, or at least partially
so. This fact lends Giordano's works their special coloring.
The atom is still a monad; in his writings, it is still something
alive. The sum of cosmic laws retains a soul quality, but not because
he experienced the soul in all the smallest details as did the
ancient mystics, and not because he experienced the mathematical laws
of the cosmos as the intentions of the spirit. No, it was because he
roused himself to wonder at this new cosmology and to glorify it
poetically in a pseudo-scientific form. Giordano Bruno is truly
something like a connecting link between two world conceptions, the
present one and the ancient one that lasted into the fifteenth
century. Man today can form scarcely any idea of the latter. All
cosmic aspects were then still experienced by man, who did not yet
differentiate between the subject within himself and the cosmic
object outside. The two were still as one; man did not speak of the
three dimensions in space, sundered from the orientation within his
own body and appearing as above-below, right-left, and
forward-backward.
Copernicus tried to grasp astronomy with abstract mathematical ideas.
On the other hand, Newton shows mathematics completely on its own.
Here I do not mean single mathematical deductions, but mathematical
thinking in general, entirely divorced from human experience. This
sounds somewhat radical and objections could certainly be made to
what I am thus describing in broad outlines, but this does not alter
the essential facts. Newton is pretty much the first to approach the
phenomena of nature with abstract mathematical thinking. Hence, as a
kind of successor to Copernicus, Newton becomes the real founder of
modern scientific thinking.
It is interesting to see in Newton's time and in the age that
followed how civilized humanity is at pains to come to terms with the
immense transformation in soul configuration that occurred as the old
mathematical-mystical view gave way to the new
mathematical-scientific style. The thinkers of the time find it
difficult to come to terms with this revolutionary change. It becomes
all the more evident when we look into the details, the specific
problems with which some of these people wrestled. See how Newton,
for instance, presents his system by trying to relate it to the
mathematics that has been severed from man. We find that he
postulates time, place, space, and motion. He says in effect in his
Principa: I need not define place, time, space, and motion
because everybody understands them.
[ 34 ]
Everybody knows what time is,
what space, place, and motion are, hence these concepts, taken from
common experience, can be used in my mathematical explanation of the
universe. People are not always fully conscious of what they say. In
life, it actually happens seldom that a person fully penetrates
everything he says with his consciousness. This is true even among
the greatest thinkers. Thus Newton really does not know why he takes
place, time, space, and motion as his starting points and feels no
need to explain or define them, whereas in all subsequent deductions
he is at pains to explain and define everything. Why does he do this?
The reasons is that in regard to place, time, motion, and space all
cleverness and thinking avail us nothing. No matter how much we think
about these concepts, we grow no wiser than we were to begin with.
Their nature is such that we experience them simply through our
common human nature and must take them as they come. A successor of
Newton's, Bishop Berkeley,
[ 35 ]
took particular notice of this point. He was involved in philosophy more
than Newton was, but Berkeley illustrates the conflicts taking place during
the emergence of scientific thinking. In other respects, as we shall presently
hear, he was not satisfied with Newton, but he was especially struck
by the way that Newton took these concepts as his basis without any
explanation, that he merely said: I start out from place, time,
space, and motion; I do not define them; I take them as premises for
my mathematical and scientific reflections. Berkeley agrees that one
must do this. One must take these concepts in the way they are
understood by the simplest person, because there they are always
clear. They become unclear not in outward experience, but in the
heads of metaphysicians and philosophers. Berkeley feels that when
these four concepts are found in life, they are clear; but they are
always obscure when found in the heads of thinkers.
It is indeed true that all thinking about these concepts is of no
avail. One feels this. Therefore, Newton is only beginning to juggle
mathematically when he uses these concepts to explain the world. He
is juggling with ideas. This is not meant in a derogatory way; I only
want to describe Newton's abilities in a telling manner. One of
the concepts thus utilized by Newton is that of space. He manipulates
the idea of space as perceived by the man in the street. Still, a
vestige of living experience is contained therein. If, on the other
hand, one pictures space in terms of Cartesian mathematics, without
harboring any illusions, it makes one's brain reel. There is
something undefinable about this space, with its arbitrary center of
coordinates. One can, for example, speculate brilliantly (and
fruitlessly) about whether Descartes’ space if finite or
infinite. Ordinary awareness of space that is still connected with
the human element really is not at all concerned with finiteness or
infinity. It is after all quite without interest to a living world
conception whether space can be pictured as finite or infinite.
Therefore one can say that Newton takes the trivial idea of space
just as he finds it, but then he begins to mathematize. But, due to
the particular quality of thinking in his age, he already has the
abstracted mathematics and geometry, and therefore he penetrates
spatial phenomena and processes of nature with abstract mathematics.
Thereby he sunders the natural phenomena from man. In fact, in
Newton's physics we meet for the first time ideas of nature
that have been completely divorced from man. Nowhere in earlier times
were conceptions of nature so torn away from man as they are in
Newtonian physics.
Going back to a thinker of the fourth or fifth century A.D. —
though people of that period can hardly be called
“thinkers,”
because their inner life was far more alive than the mere life in
thoughts — we would find that he held the view: “I live;
I experience space along with my God, and orient myself in space
up-and-down, right-left, and forward-backward, but I dwell in space
together with my God. He outlines the directions and I experience
them.” So it was for a thinker of the third or fourth century
A.D. and even later; indeed, it only became different in the
fourteenth century. Thinking geometrically about space, man did not
merely draw a triangle but was conscious of the fact that, while he
did this, God dwelled within him and drew along with him. His
experience was qualitative; he drew the qualitative reality that God
Himself had placed within him. Everywhere in the outer world,
whenever mathematics was observed, the intentions of God were also
observed.
By Newton's time mathematics has become abstracted. Man has
forgotten that originally he received mathematics as an inspiration
from God. And in this utterly abstract form, Newton now applies
mathematics to the study of space. As he writes his Principia, he
simply applies this abstracted mathematics, this idea of space (which
he does not define,) because he has a dim feeling that nothing will
be gained by trying to define it. He takes the trivial idea of space
and applies his abstract mathematics to it, thus severing it from any
inward experiences. This is how he speaks of the principles of
nature.
Later on, interestingly enough, Newton goes somewhat deeper. This is
easy to see if one is familiar with his works. Newton becomes ill at
ease, as it were, when he contemplates his own view of space. He is
not quite comfortable with this space, torn as it is out of man and
estranged completely from the spirit. So he defines it after all,
saying that space is the sensorium of God. It is most interesting
that at the starting point of modern science the very person who was
the first to completely mathematize and separate space from man,
eventually defines space as God's sensorium,
[ 36 ]
a sort of brain or sense organ of God. Newton had torn nature asunder into
space and man-who-experiences-space. Having done this, he feels inwardly uneasy
when he views this abstract space, which man had formerly experienced
in union with his god. Formerly, man had said to himself: What my
human sensorium experiences in space, I experience together with my
god. Newton becomes uneasy, now that he has torn space away form the
human sensorium. He has thereby torn himself away from his permeation
with the divine-spiritual. Space, with all is mathematics, was not
something external. So, in later life, Newton addresses it as
God's
sensorium, though to begin with he had torn the whole apart, thus
leaving space devoid of Spirit and God. But enough feeling remained
in Newton that he could not leave this externalized space devoid of
God. So he deified it again.
Scientifically, man tore himself loose from his god, and thus from
the spirit; but outwardly he again postulated the same spirit. What
happened here explains why a man like Goethe found it impossible
[ 37 ]
to go along with Newton on any point. Goethe's Theory of Color is
one particularly characteristic point. This whole procedure of first
casting out the spirit, separating it from man, was foreign to
Goethe's nature. Goethe always had the feeling that man has to
experience everything, even what is related to the cosmos. Even in
regard to the three dimensions Goethe felt that the cosmos was only a
continuation of what man had inwardly experienced. Therefore Goethe
was by nature Newton's adversary.
Now let us return to Berkeley, who was somewhat younger than Newton,
but still belonged to the period of conflict that accompanied the
rise of the scientific way of thinking. Berkeley had no quarrel with
Newton's accepting the trivial ideas of place, space, time, and
motion. But he was not happy with this whole science that was
emerging, and particularly not with its interpretations of natural
phenomena. It was evident to him that when nature is utterly severed
from man it cannot be experienced at all, and that man is deceiving
himself when he imagines that he is experiencing it.
Therefore, Berkeley declared that bodies forming the external basis
for sense perceptions do not really exist. Reality is spiritual
through and through. The universe, as it appears to us — even
where it appears in a bodily form — is but the manifestation of
an all-pervading spirit. In Berkeley, these ideas appear pretty much
as mere assertions, for he no longer had any trace of the old
mysticism and even less of the ancient pneumatology. Except for his
religious dogma, he really had no ground at all for his assertion of
such all-pervading spirituality. But assert it he did, and so
vigorously that all corporeality become for him no more than a
revelation of the spirit. Hence it was impossible for Berkeley to
say: I behold a color and there is vibrating movement back of it that
I cannot see — which is what modern science justifiably states.
Instead, Berkeley said: I cannot hypothetically assume that there is
anything possessing any corporeal property such as vibratory
movement. The basis of the physical world of phenomena must be
spiritually conceived. Something spiritual is behind a color
perception as its cause, which I experience in myself when I know
myself as spirit. Thus Berkeley is a spiritualist in the sense in
which this term is used in German philosophy.
For dogmatic reasons, but with a certain justification, Berkeley
makes innumerable objections against the assumption that nature can
be comprehended by mathematics that has been abstracted from direct
experience. Since to Berkeley the whole cosmos was spiritual, he also
viewed mathematics as having been formed together with the spirit of
the cosmos. He held that we do in fact experience the intentions of
the cosmic spirit insofar as they have mathematical forms, for that
we cannot apply mathematical concepts in an external manner to
corporeal objects.
In accordance with this point of view, Berkeley opposed what
mathematics had become for both Newton and Leibnitz,
[ 38 ]
namely differential and integral calculus. Please, do not misunderstand me.
Today's lecture must be fashioned in such a way that it cannot
but provoke many objections in one who holds to the views prevailing
today. But these objections will fade away during the ensuring
lectures, if one is willing to keep an open mind. Today, however, I
want to present the themes that will occupy us in a rather radical
form.
Berkeley became an opponent of the whole infinitesimal calculus
[ 39 ]
to the extent that it was then known. He opposed what was beyond
experience. In this regard, Berkeley's feeling for things was
often more sensitive than his thoughts. He felt how, to the
quantities that the mind could conceive, the emergence of
infinitesimal calculus added other quantities; namely, the
differentials, which attain definition only in the differential
coefficient. Differentials must be conceived in such a way that they
always elude our thinking, as it were. Our thinking refuses to
completely permeate them. Berkeley regarded this as a loss of
reality, since knowledge for him was only what could be experienced.
Therefore he could not approve of mathematical ideas that produced
the indetermination of the differentials.
What are we really doing when we seek differential equations for
natural phenomena? We are pointing to something that eludes our
possible experience. I realize, of course, that many of you cannot
quite follow me on these points, but I cannot here expound the whole
nature of infinitesimal calculus. I only want to draw attention to
some aspects that will contribute to our study of the birth of modern
science.
Modern science set out to master the natural phenomena by means of a
mathematics detached from man, a mathematics no longer inwardly
experienced. By adopting this abstract mathematical view and these
concepts divorced from man, science arrived at a point where it could
examine only the inanimate. Having taken mathematics out of the
sphere of live experience, one can only apply it to what is dead.
Therefore, owing to this mathematical approach, modern science is
directed exclusively to the sphere of death. In the universe, death
manifests itself in disintegration, in atomization, in reduction to
microscopic parts — putting it simply, in a crumbling into
dust. This is the direction taken by the present-day scientific
attitude. With a mathematics detached from all living experience, it
takes hold of everything in the cosmos that turns to dust, that
atomizes. From this moment onward it becomes possible to dissipate
mathematics itself into differentials. We actually kill all living
forms of thought, if we try to penetrate them with any kind of
differential equation, with any differential line of thought. To
differentiate is to kill; to integrate is to piece the dead together
again in some kind of framework, to fit the differentials together
again into a whole. But they do not thereby become alive again, after
having been annihilated. One ends up with dead specters, not with
anything living.
This is how the whole perspective of what was opening up through
infinitesimal calculus appeared to Berkeley. Had he expressed himself
concretely, he might well have said: First you kill the whole world
by differentiating it; then you fit its differentials together again
in integrals, but you no longer have a world, only a copy, an
illusion. With regard to its content, every integral is really an
illusion, and Berkeley already felt this to be so. Therefore,
differentiation really implies annihilation, while integration is the
gathering up of bones and dust, so that the earlier forms of the
slain beings can be pieced together again. But this does not bring
them back to life; they remain no more than dead replicas.
One can say that Berkeley's sentiments were untimely. This they
certainly were, for the new way of approach had to come. Anyone who
would have said that infinitesimal calculus should never have been
developed would have been called not a scientific thinker but a fool.
On the other hand, one must realize that at the outset of this whole
stream of development, feelings such as Berkeley's were
understandable. He shuddered at what he thought would come from a
infinitesimal study of nature and had to do with the process of birth
but a study of all dying aspects in nature.
Formerly this had not been observed, nor had there been any interest
in it. In earlier times, the coming-into-being, the germinating, had
been studied; now, one looked at all that was fading and crumbling
into dust. Man's conception was heading toward atomism, whereas
previously it had tended toward the continuous, lasting aspects of
things. Since life cannot exist without death and all living things
must die, we must look at and understand all that is dead in the
world. A science of the inanimate, the dead, had to arise. It was
absolutely necessary. The time that we are speaking about was the age
in which mankind was ready for such a science. But we must visualize
how this went against the grain of somebody who, like Berkeley, still
lived completely in the old view.
The after-effects of what came into being then are still very much
with us today. We have witnessed the triumphs of just those
scientific labors that made Berkeley shudder. Until they were
somewhat modified through the modern theory of relativity,
[ 40 ]
Newton's
theories reigned supreme, Goethe's revolt against them made no
impression. For a true comprehension of what went on we must go back
to Newton's time and see the shuddering of thinkers who still
had a vivid recollection of earlier views and how they clung to
feelings that resembled the former ones.
Giordano Bruno shrank from studying the dead nature that was now to
be the object of study. He could not view it as dead in a purely
mathematical manner of thought, so he animated the atoms into monads
and imbued his mathematical thinking with poetry in order to retain
it in a personal sphere. Newton at first proceeded from a purely
mathematical standpoint, but then he wavered and defined space (which
he has first completely divorced from man through his external
mathematics) as God's sensorium. Berkeley in his turn rejected
the new direction of thinking altogether and with it the whole trend
towards the infinitesimal.
Today, however, we are surrounded and overwhelmed by the world view
that Giordano Bruno tried to turn into poetry, that Newton felt
uncomfortable about, and that Berkeley completely rejected. Do we
take what Newton said — that space is a sensorium of God —
seriously when we think in the accepted scientific sense today?
People today like to regard as great thinkers those men who have said
something or other that they approve. But if the great men also said
something that they do not approve, they feel very superior and
think: Unfortunately, on this point he wasn’t as enlightened as
I am. Thus many people consider Lessing
[ 41 ]
a man of great genius but
make an exception for what he did toward the end of his life, when he
became convinced that we go through repeated earth lives.
Just because we must in the present age come to terms with the ideas
that have arisen, we must go back to their origin. Since mathematics
has once and for all been detached from man, and since nature has
been taken hold of by this abstract mathematics that has gradually
isolated us from the whole of nature, we must now somehow manage to
find ourselves in this nature. For we will not attain a coherent
spiritual knowledge until we once again have found the spirit in
nature.
Just as it is a matter of course that every living man will sooner or
later die, so it was a matter of course that sooner or later in the
course of time a conception of death had to emerge from the former
life-imbued world view. Things that can only be learned from a corpse
cannot be learned by a person who is unwilling to examine the corpse.
Therefore certain mysteries of the world can be comprehended only if
the modern scientific way of thinking is taken seriously.
Let me close with a somewhat personal remark.
[ 42 ]
The scientific world view must be taken seriously, and for this reason I was
never an opponent of it; on the contrary, I regarded it as something that of
necessity belongs to our time. Often I had to speak out against
something that a scientist, or so-called scientist, had made of the
things that were discovered by unprejudiced investigation of the
sphere of death. It was the misinterpretation of such scientific
discoveries that I opposed. On this occasion let me state
emphatically that I do not wish to be regarded as in any way an
opponent of the scientific approach. I would consider it detrimental
to all our anthroposophical endeavors if a false opposition were to
arise between what anthroposophy seeks by way of spiritual research
and what science seeks — and must of necessity seek in its
field — out of the modern attitude.
I say this expressly, my dear friends, because a healthy discussion
concerning the relationship between anthroposophy and science must
come to pass within our movement. Anything that goes wrong in this
respect can only do grave harm to anthroposophy and should be
avoided.
I mention this here because recently, in preparing these lectures, I
read in the anthroposophical periodical Die Drei that atomism
was being studied in a way in which no progress can be made.
Therefore, I want to make it clear that I consider all these polemics
in Die Drei about atomism as something that only serves to
stultify the relations between anthroposophy and science.
|