Yesterday we discussed the nature of will in so far as will is
embodied in the human organ. Today we will use this knowledge of man's
relationship to will to fructify our consideration of the rest of the
human being.
You will have noticed that in treating of the human being up to now I
have chiefly drawn attention to the intellectual activity, the
activity of cognition, on the one hand, and the activity of will on
the other hand. I have shown you how the activity of cognition has a
close connection with the nerve nature of the human being, and how the
activity of will has a close connection with the activity of the
blood. If you think this over you will also want to know what can be
said with regard to the third soul power, that is, the activity of
feeling. We have not yet given this much consideration, but today, by
thinking more of the activity of feeling, we shall have the
opportunity of entering more intensively into an understanding of the
two other sides of human nature, namely cognition and will.
Now there is one thing that we must be clear about, and this I have
already mentioned in various connections. We cannot put the soul
powers pedantically side by side, separate from each other, thus:
thinking, feeling, willing, because in the living soul, in its
entirety, one activity is always merging into another.
Consider the will on the one hand. You will realise that you cannot
bring your will to bear on anything that you do not represent to
yourself as mental picture, that you do not permeate with the activity
of cognition. Try in self-contemplation, even superficially, to
concentrate on your willing, you will find that in every act of will
the mental picture is present in some form. You could not be a human
being at all if mental picturing were not involved in your acts
of will. And your willing would proceed from a dull instinctive
activity, if you did not permeate the action which springs forth from
the will with the activity of thought, of mental picturing.
Just as thought is present in every act of will, so will is to be
found in all thinking. Again, even a purely superficial contemplation
of your own self will show you that in thinking you always let your
will stream into the formation of your thoughts. In the forming of
your own thoughts, in the uniting of one thought with another, or
passing over to judgments and conclusions in all this there
streams a delicate current of will.
Thus actually we can only say that will activity is chiefly will
activity and has an undercurrent of thought within it; and thought
activity is chiefly thought activity and has an undercurrent of will.
Thus, in considering the separate faculties of soul, it is impossible
to place them side-by-side in a pedantic way, because one flows into
the other.
Now this flowing into one another of the soul activities, which is
recognisable in the soul, is also to be seen in the body, where the
soul activity comes to expression. For instance, let us look at the
human eye. If we look at it in its totality we shall see that the
nerves are continued right into the eye itself; but so also are the
blood vessels. The presence of the nerves enables the activity of
thought and cognition to stream into the eye of the human being; and
the presence of the blood vessels enables the will activity to stream
in. So also in the body as a whole, right into the periphery of the
sense activities, the elements of will on the one hand and thought or
cognition on the other hand are bound up with each other. This applies
to all the senses and moreover it applies to the limbs, which serve
the will: the element of cognition enters into our willing and into
our movements through the nerves, and the element of will enters in
through the blood vessels.
But now we must also learn the special nature of the activities of
cognition. We have already spoken of this, but we must be fully
conscious of the whole complex belonging to this side of human
activity, to thought and cognition. As we have already said, in
cognition, in mental picturing lives antipathy. However strange it may
seem, everything connected with mental picturing, with thought, is
permeated with antipathy. You will probably say, Yes, but when I
look at something I am not exercising any antipathy in this
looking. But indeed you do exercise it. When you look at an
object, you exercise antipathy. If nerve activity alone were present
in your eye, everything you looked at would be an object of disgust to
you, would be absolutely antipathetic to you. But the will, which is
made up of sympathy, also pours its activity into the eye, that is,
the blood in its physical form penetrates into the eye, and it is only
by this means that the feeling of antipathy in sense-perception is
overcome in your consciousness, and the objective, neutral act of
sight is brought about by the balance between sympathy and antipathy.
It is brought about by the fact that sympathy and antipathy balance
one another, and by the fact also that we are quite unconscious of
this interplay between sympathy and antipathy.
If you take Goethe's Theory of Colour, to which I have already
referred in this connection, and study especially the
physiological-didactic part of it, you will see that it is because
Goethe goes more deeply into the activity of sight that there
immediately enters into his consideration of the finer shades of
colour the elements of sympathy and antipathy. As soon as you begin to
enter into the activity of a sense organ you discover the elements of
sympathy and antipathy which arise in that activity. Thus in the sense
activity itself the antipathetic element comes from the actual
cognitive part, from mental picturing, the nerve part and the
sympathetic element comes from the will part, from the blood.
As I have often pointed out in general anthroposophical lectures there
is a very important difference between animals and man with regard to
the constitution of the eye. It is a significant characteristic of the
animal that it has much more blood activity in its eye than the human
being. In certain animals you will even find organs which are given up
to this blood activity, as for example the ensiform cartilage, or the
fan. From this you can deduce that the animal sends much
more blood activity into the eye than the human being, and this is
also the case with the other senses. That is to say, in his senses the
animal develops much more sympathy, instinctive sympathy with his
environment than the human being does. The human being has in reality
more antipathy to his environment than the animal only this antipathy
does not come into consciousness in ordinary life. It only comes into
consciousness when our perception of the external world is intensified
to a degree of impression to which we react with disgust. This is only
a heightened impression of all sense-perceptions; you react with
disgust to the external impression. When you go to a place that has a
bad smell and you feel disgust within the range of this smell, then
this feeling of disgust is nothing more than an intensification of
what takes place in every sense activity, only that the disgust which
accompanies the feeling in the sense impression remains as a rule
below the threshold of consciousness. But if we human beings had no
more antipathy to our environment than the animal, we should not
separate ourselves off so markedly from our environment as we actually
do. The animal has much more sympathy with his environment, and has
therefore grown together with it much more, and hence he is much more
dependent on climate, seasons, etc., than the human being is. It is
because man has much more antipathy to his environment than the animal
has that he is a personality. We have our separate consciousness of
personality because the antipathy which lies below the threshold of
consciousness enables us to separate ourselves from our environment.
Now this brings us to something which plays an important part in our
comprehension of man. We have seen how in the activity of thought
there flow together thinking (nerve activity as expressed in terms of
the body) and willing (blood activity as expressed in terms of the
body). But in the same way there flow together in actions of will the
real will activity and the activity of thought. When we will to do
something, we always develop sympathy for what we wish to do. But it
would get no further than an instinctive willing unless we could bring
antipathy also into willing, and thus separate ourselves as
personalities from the action which we intend to perform. But the
sympathy for what we plan to do is predominant, and a balance is only
effected by the fact that we bring in antipathy also. Hence it comes
about that the sympathy as such lies below the threshold of
consciousness, and part of it only enters consciously into that which
is willed. In all the numerous actions that we perform not merely out
of our reason but with real enthusiasm, and with love and devotion,
sympathy predominates so strongly in the will that it penetrates into
the consciousness above the threshold, and our willing itself appears
charged with sympathy, whereas as a rule it merely unites us with our
environment in an objective way. Just as it is only in exceptional
circumstances that our antipathy to the environment may become
conscious in cognition, so our sympathy with the environment (which is
always present) may only become conscious in exceptional
circumstances, namely, when we act with enthusiasm and loving
devotion. Otherwise we should perform all our actions instinctively.
We should never be able to relate ourselves properly to the objective
demands of the world, for example in social life. We must permeate our
will with thinking, so that this will may make us members of all
humanity and partakers in the world's process itself.
Perhaps it will be clear to you what really happens if you think what
chaos there would be in the human soul if we were perpetually
conscious of all this that I have spoken of. For if this were the case
man would be conscious of a considerable amount of antipathy
accompanying all his actions. This would be terrible! Man would then
pass through the world feeling himself continually in an atmosphere of
antipathy. It is wisely ordered that this antipathy as a force is
indeed essential to our actions, but that we should not be aware of
it, that it should lie below the threshold of consciousness.
Now in this connection we touch upon a wonderful mystery of human
nature, a mystery which can be felt by any person of perception, but
which the teacher and educator must bring to full consciousness. In
early childhood we act more or less out of pure sympathy, however
strange this may seem; all a child does, all its romping and play, it
does out of sympathy with the deed, with the romping. When sympathy is
born in the world it is strong love, strong willing. But it cannot
remain in this condition, it must be permeated with thought, by idea,
it must be continuously illumined as it were by the conscious mental
picture. This takes place in a comprehensive way if we bring ideals,
moral ideals, into our mere instincts. And now you will understand
better the true significance of antipathy in this connection. If the
impulses that we notice in the little child were throughout our life
to remain only sympathetic, as they are sympathetic in childhood, we
should develop in an animal way under the influence of our instincts.
These instincts must become antipathetic to us; we must pour antipathy
into them. When we pour antipathy into them we do it by means of our
moral ideals, to which the instincts are antipathetic, and which for
our life between birth and death bring antipathy into the childlike
sympathy of instincts. For this reason moral development is always
somewhat ascetic. But this asceticism must be rightly understood. It
always betokens an exercise in the combating of the animal element.
This can show us to what a great extent willing in man's practical
activity is not merely willing but is also permeated with idea, with
the activity of cognition, of mental picturing.
Now between cognition or thinking on the one hand and willing on the
other hand we find the human activity of feeling. If you picture to
yourselves what I have now put forward as willing and as thinking, you
can say: From a certain central boundary there stream forth on the one
hand all that is sympathy, willing, and on the other hand all that is
antipathy, thinking. But the sympathy of willing also works back into
thinking, and the antipathy of thinking works over into willing. Thus
man is a unity because what is developed principally on the one side
plays over into the other. Now between the two, between thinking and
willing, there lies feeling, and this feeling is related to thinking
on the one hand and to willing on the other hand. In the soul as a
whole you cannot keep thought and will strictly apart, and still less
can you keep the thought and will elements apart in feeling. In
feeling, the will and thought elements are very strongly intermingled.
Here again you can convince yourselves of the truth of these remarks
by even the most superficial self-examination. What I have already
said will lead you to this conviction, for I told you that willing,
which in ordinary life proceeds in an objective way, can be
intensified to an activity done out of enthusiasm and love. Then you
will clearly see willing as permeated with feeling that willing
which otherwise springs forth from the necessities of external life.
When you do something which is filled with love or enthusiasm, that
action flows out of a willing which you have allowed to become
permeated by a subjective feeling. But if you examine the sense
activities closely with the help of Goethe's theory of colour
you will see how these are also permeated by feeling. And if
the sense activity is enhanced to a condition of disgust, or on the
other hand to the point of drinking in the pleasant scent of a flower,
then you have the feeling activity flowing over directly into the
activity of the senses.
But feeling also flows over into thought. There was once a philosophic
dispute which at all events externally was of great
significance there have indeed been many such in the history of
philosophy between the psychologist Franz Brentano and the
logician Sigwart, in Heidelberg. These two gentlemen were arguing
about what it is that is present in man's power of judgment. Sigwart
said: When a man forms a judgment, and says, for example,
Man should be good; then feeling always has a voice in a
judgment of this kind; decision concerns feeling. But Brentano
said, Judgment and feeling (which latter consists of emotions)
are so different that the faculty of judgment could not be understood
at all if one imagined that feeling played into it. He meant
that in this case something subjective would play into judgment, which
ought to be purely objective.
Anyone who has a real understanding for these things will see from a
dispute of this kind that neither the psychologists nor the logicians
have discovered the real facts of the case, namely that the soul
activities are always flowing into one another. Now consider what it
is that should really be observed here. On the one hand we have
judgment, which must of course form an opinion upon something quite
objective. The fact that man should be good must not be dependent on
our subjective feeling. The content of the judgment must be objective.
But when we form a judgment something else comes into consideration
which is of a different character. Those things which are objectively
correct are not on that account consciously present in our souls. We
must first receive them consciously into our soul. And we cannot
consciously receive any judgment into our soul without the
co-operation of feeling. Therefore, we must say that Brentano and
Sigwart should have joined forces and said: True, the objective
content of the judgment remains firmly fixed outside the realm of
feeling, but in order that the subjective human soul may become
convinced of the rightness of the judgment, feeling must develop.
From this you will see how difficult it is to get any kind of exact
concepts in the inaccurate state of philosophic study which prevails
to day. One must rise to a different level before one can reach such
exact concepts, and there is no education in exact concepts to-day
except by way of spiritual science. External science imagines that it
has exact concepts, and rejects what anthroposophical spiritual
science has to give, because it has no conception that the concepts
arrived at by spiritual science are by comparison more exact and
definite than those commonly in use to-day, since they are derived
from reality and not from a mere playing with words.
When you thus trace the element of feeling on the one hand in
cognition, in mental picturing, and on the other hand in willing, then
you will say: feeling stands as a soul activity midway between
cognition and willing, and radiates its nature out in both directions.
Feeling is cognition which has not yet come fully into being, and it
is also will which has not yet fully come into being; it is cognition
in reserve, and will in reserve. Hence feeling also, is composed of
sympathy and antipathy, which as you have seen are only
present in a hidden form both in thinking and in willing. Both
sympathy and antipathy are present in cognition and in will, in the
working together of nerves and blood in the body, but they are present
in a hidden form. In feeling they become manifest.
Now what do the manifestations of feeling in the body look like? You
will find places all over the human body where the blood vessels touch
the nerves in some way. Now wherever blood vessels and nerves make
contact feeling arises. But in certain places, e.g., in the senses,
the nerves and the blood are so refined that we no longer perceive the
feeling. There is a fine undercurrent of feeling in all our seeing and
hearing, but we do not notice it, and the more the sense organ is
separated from the rest of the body, the less do we notice it. In
looking, in the eye's activity, we hardly notice the feelings of
sympathy and antipathy because the eye, embedded in its bony hollow,
is almost completely separated from the rest of the organism. And the
nerves which extend into the eye are of a very delicate nature and so
are the blood vessels which enter into the eye. The sense of feeling
in the eye is very strongly suppressed.
In the sense of hearing it is less suppressed. Hearing has much more
of an organic connection with the activity of the whole organism than
sight has. There are numerous organs within the ear which are quite
different from those of the eye, and the ear is thus in many ways a
true picture of what is at work in the whole organism. Therefore the
sense activity which goes on in the ear is very closely accompanied by
feeling. And here even people who are good judges of what they hear
find it difficult to discriminate clearly especially in the
artistic sphere between what is purely thought-element and what
is really feeling. This fact explains a very interesting historical
phenomenon of recent times, one which has even influenced actual
artistic production.
You all know the figure of Beckmesser in Richard Wagner's
Meistersinger. What is Beckmesser really supposed to
represent? He is supposed to represent a musical connoisseur who quite
forgets how the feeling element in the whole human being works into
the thought element in the activity of hearing. Wagner, who
represented his own conceptions in Walther, was, quite one-sidedly,
permeated with the idea that it is chiefly the feeling element that
should dwell in music. In the contrast between Walther and Beckmesser,
arising out of a mistaken conception I mean mistaken on both
sides we see the antithesis of the right conception, viz. that
feeling and thinking work together in the hearing of music. And this
came to be expressed in a historical phenomenon, because as soon as
Wagnerian art appeared, or became at all well known, it found an
opponent in the person of Eduard Hanslick of Vienna, who looked upon
the whole appeal to feeling in Wagner's art as unmusical. There are
few works on art which are so interesting from a psychological point
of view as the work of Eduard Hanslick On Beauty in Music. The
chief thought in this book is that whoever would derive everything in
music from a feeling element is no true musician, and has no real
understanding for music: for a true musician sees the real essence of
what is musical only in the objective joining of one tone with
another, and in Arabesque which builds itself up from tone to tone,
abstaining from all feeling. In this book, On Beauty in Music
Hanslick then works out with wonderful purity his claim that the
highest type of music must consist solely in the tone-picture, the
tone Arabesque. He pours unmitigated scorn upon the idea which is
really the very essence of Wagnerism, namely that tunes should be
created out of the element of feeling. The very fact that such a
dispute as this between Hanslick and Wagner could arise in the sphere
of music is a clear sign that recent psychological ideas about the
activities of the soul have been completely confused, otherwise this
one-sided idea of Hanslick's could never have arisen. But if we
recognise the one-sidedness and then devote ourselves to the study of
Hanslick's ideas which have a certain philosophical strength in them,
we shall come to the conclusion that the little book On Beauty in
Music is very brilliant.
From this you will see that, regarding the human being for the moment
as feeling being, some senses bear more, some less of this whole human
being into the periphery of the body, in consciousness.
Now in your task of gaining educational insight it behoves you to
consider something which is bringing chaos into the scientific
thinking of the present day. Had I not given you these talks as a
preparation for the practical reforms you will have to undertake, then
you would have had to plan your educational work for yourselves from
the pedagogical theories of to-day, from the existing psychologies and
systems of logic and from the educational practice of the present
time. You would have had to carry into your schoolwork the customary
thoughts of the present day. But these thoughts are in a very bad
state even with regard to psychology. In every psychology you find a
so-called theory of the senses. In investigating the basis of
sense-activity the psychologist simply lumps together the activity of
the eye, the ear, the nose, etc., all in one great abstraction as
sense-activity. This is a very grave mistake, a serious
error. For if you take only those senses which are known to the
psychologist or physiologist of to-day and consider them in their
bodily aspect alone, you will notice that the sense of the eye is
quite different from the sense of the ear. Eye and ear are two quite
different organisms not to speak of the organisation of the
sense of touch which has not been investigated at all as yet, not even
in the gratifying manner in which eye and ear have been investigated.
But let us keep to the consideration of the eye and ear. They perform
two quite different activities so that to class seeing and hearing
together as general sense-activity is merely grey
theory. The right way to set to work here would be to speak from
a concrete point of view only of the activity of the eye, the
activity of the ear, the activity of the organ of smell, etc. Then we
should find such a great difference between them that we should lose
all desire to put forward a general physiology of the senses as the
psychologies of to-day have done.
In studying the human soul we only gain true insight if we remain
within the sphere which I have endeavoured to outline in my
Truth and Science,
and also in
The Philosophy of Freedom.
Here we can speak of the soul as a single entity without falling into
abstractions. For here we stand upon a sure foundation; we proceed
from the point of view that man lives his way into the world, and does
not at first possess the whole of reality. You can study this in
Truth and Science,
and in
The Philosophy of Freedom.
To begin with man has not the whole reality; he has first to develop
himself further, and in this further development what formerly was not
yet reality becomes true reality for him through the interplay of
thinking and perception. Man first has to win reality. In this
connection Kantianism, which has eaten its way into everything, has
wrought the most terrible havoc. What does Kantianism do? First of all
it says dogmatically: we look out upon the world that is round about
us, and within us there lives only the mirrored image of this world.
And so it comes to all its other deductions. Kant himself is not clear
as to what is in the environment which man perceives. For reality is
not within the environment, nor is it in phenomena: only gradually,
through our own winning of it, does reality come in sight, and the
first sight of reality is the last thing we get. Strictly speaking,
true reality would be what man sees in the moment when he can no
longer express himself, the moment in which he passes through the
gateway of death.
Many false elements have entered into our civilisation, and these work
at their deepest in the sphere of education. Therefore we must strive
to put true conceptions in the place of the false. Then, also, shall
we be able to do what we have to do for our teaching in the right way.
|