VII
Reference to the Experience of the
Individual Reader
(See Exposition on Brief, Chapter 7)
W
E WOULD
avoid the fallacy of attributing a
characteristic a priori to the immediately
given, to the first form in which the outer and the inner world
appear to us, and then establishing the validity of our reasoning on
the basis of this presupposition. Indeed, by our very
definition, experience is that in which thinking has no share. There
cannot be any charge, therefore, of an error in thinking at the
outset of our discussion.
It is just here that the fundamental
fallacy arises in many scientific endeavors, especially at the
present time. Such scientists imagine that they are reproducing pure
experience, whereas they are really reading again concepts which they
themselves have interjected into the content of experience. It
may be charged that we also have assigned a number of attributes to
pure experience. We described it as endless multiplicity, as an
aggregate of unrelated units, etc. Are not these also
characterizations made by thought? Certainly not in the sense in
which we have used them. We have made use of these concepts only to
fix the reader's attention upon reality free from thought. We
do not desire to attribute these concepts to experience; we employ
them only to direct attention to that form of reality which is
void of any concept whatever.
All scientific
inquiries must naturally be conducted by means of language, and
language can express nothing except concepts. But there is an
essential difference between employing certain words for the purpose
of directly attributing this or that characteristic to a thing,
on the one hand, and, on the other, employing these words
merely to direct the reader's or the hearer's attention to an
object. If we may resort to an analogy, we might say: These are two
different things, when A says on the one hand to B: “Observe
that man in his family circle, and you will form an essentially
different opinion of him from that which you form of him in his
official behavior;” and, on the other hand, when he says:
“That man is an excellent father to his family.” In the
first instance the attention of B is attracted in a certain manner;
he is advised to form a judgment of a certain person under
certain circumstances. In the second instance a certain
characteristic is attributed to this person, and therefore an
assertion is made. As the first case here compares with the second,
so does our initial step in the discussion compare with similar
phenomena in literature. Since the exigencies of style or the
difficulty of expressing our thought may at times give to the
matter a different appearance, we wish to declare expressly at this
point that our discussion is to be taken only in the sense here
explained and is far removed from any pretension of having advanced
any assertion whatever which holds good of things in
themselves.
If, now, we are to have a name for
the first form in which we observe reality, we are convinced that the
name most adequately applicable is to be found in the expression
“appearance to the senses.” We here understand by the
termsense
not only the external senses, mediators of the
external world, but all bodily and mental organs whatsoever which
have to do with our becoming aware of the immediate facts.
Indeed, the terminner
sense is quite ordinarily
used in psychology for the perceptive capacity as to inner
experience.
By the termappearance, however, we
would designate merely a thing perceptible to us or a perceptible
occurrence in so far as this appears in space or
time.
Here we must raise
still another question, which will bring us to the second factor that
we must observe in relation to the science of cognition — that
is, thinking.
Must we regard the
form in which experience has hitherto been recognized by us as
something rooted in the nature of things? Is it a characteristic of
reality?
(See Notes to the New Edition, 1924, page 29)
Much depends upon the answer to this
question. That is, if this form is an essential characteristic of the
things of experience, something which belongs to them by their nature
in the truest sense of the word, then it is impossible to see how
this stage of knowledge can ever be surmounted. We should simply have
to apply ourselves to the task of making unrelated notes of all that
we experience, and such an assemblage of notes would constitute
our science. For what could all research into the
interrelationships of things accomplish if the complete
isolated-ness characterizing them in the form of experience
represented their real nature?
The state of the
case will be entirely different if in this form of reality we have to
do, not with its essential nature, but only with its quite
unessential external aspect; if we have before us only a shell of the
true nature of the world which conceals that nature from us and
requires us to search further for it. In that case, we should have to
strive to break through this shell. We should have to proceed from
this first form of the world in order to master its true
characteristics (those essential to its being). We should have to
surmount the “appearance for the senses” in order to
unfold out of this a higher form of appearance.
The answer to this
question is given in the following inquiries.
|