Darwinism and World Conception
If the thought of the teleological structure of nature was to be
reformed in the sense of a naturalistic world conception, the
purpose-adjusted formation of the organic world had to be explained in
the same fashion as the physicist or the chemist explains the lifeless
processes. When a magnet attracts iron shavings, no physicist will
assume that there is a force at work in the magnet that aims toward
the purpose of the attraction. When hydrogen and oxygen form water as
a compound, the chemist does not interpret this process as if
something in both substances had been actively striving toward the
purpose of forming water. An explanation of living beings that is
guided by a similar naturalistic mode of thinking must conclude that
organisms become purpose-adjusted without anything in nature planning
this purpose-conformity. This conformity comes to pass without being
anywhere intended. Such an explanation was given by Charles Darwin. He
took the point of view that there is nothing in nature that plans the
design. Nature is never in a position to consider whether its products
are adequate to a purpose or not. It produces without choosing between
what is adequate to a purpose and what is not.
What is the meaning of this distinction anyhow? When is a thing in
conformity with a purpose? Is it not when it is so arranged that the
external circumstances correspond to its needs, to its life
conditions? A thing is inadequate to purpose when this is not the
case. What will happen if, while a complete absence of plan in nature
characterizes the situation, formations of all degrees of
purpose-conformity, from the most to the least adequately adapted
form, come into existence? Every being will attempt to adapt its
existence to the given circumstances. A being well-adjusted to life
will do so without much difficulty; one less adequately endowed will
succeed only to a lesser degree. The fact must be added to this that
nature is not a parsimonious housekeeper in regard to the production
of living beings. The number of germs is prodigious. The abundant
production of germs is backed up by inadequate means for the support
of life. The effect of this will be that those beings that are better
adapted to the acquisition of food will more easily succeed in their
development. A well-adapted organic being will prevail in the strife
for existence over a less adequately adjusted one. The latter must
perish in this competition. The fit, that is to say, the one adapted
to the purpose of life, survives; the unfit, that is, the one not so
adapted, does not. This is the struggle for life. Thus,
the forms adequate to the purpose of life are preserved even if nature
itself produces, without choice, the inadequate side by side with the
adequate. Through a law, then, that is as objective and as devoid of
any wise purpose as any mathematical or mechanical law of nature can
be, the course of nature's evolution receives a tendency toward a
purpose-conformity that is not originally inherent in it.
Darwin was led to this thought through the work of the social
economist Malthus entitled Essay on the Principle of Population
(1798). In this essay the view is advanced that there is a
perpetual competition going on in human society because the population
grows at a much faster pace than the supply of food. This law that
Malthus had stated as valid for the history of mankind, was
generalized by Darwin into a comprehensive law of the whole world of
life.
Darwin now set out to show how this struggle for existence becomes the
creator of the various forms of living beings and that thereby the old
principle of Linnaeus was overthrown, that we have to count as
many species in the animals and vegetable kingdoms as had been
principally created. The doubt against this principle was
clearly formed in Darwin's mind when, in the years 1831 36, he was
on a journey to South America and Australia. He tells how this doubt
took shape in him.
When I visited the Galapagos Archipelago during my journey on
H.M.S. Beagle, at a distance of about 500 miles from the shores
of South America, I saw myself surrounded by strange species of birds,
reptiles and snakes, which exist nowhere else in the world. Almost all
of them bore the unmistakable stamp of the American continent. In the
song of the mocking-thrush, in the sharp scream of the vultures, in
the large candlestick-like opuntias I noticed distinctly the vicinity
of America; and yet these islands were separated from the continent by
many miles and were very different in their geological constitution
and their climate. Even more surprising was the fact that most of the
inhabitants of each of the individual islands of the small archipelago
were specifically different although closely related. I often asked
myself how these strange animals and men had come into being. The
simplest way seemed to be that the inhabitants of the various islands
were descended from one another and had undergone modifications in the
course of their descent, and that all inhabitants of the archipelago
were descendants of those of the nearest continent, namely, America,
where the colonization naturally would have its origin. But it was for
a long time an unexplainable problem to me how the necessary
modification could have been obtained.
The answer to this question is contained in the naturalistic
conception of the evolution of the living organism. As the physicist
subjects a substance to different conditions in order to study its
properties, so Darwin, after his return, observed the phenomena that
resulted in living beings under different circumstances. He made
experiments in breeding pigeons, chickens, dogs, rabbits and plants.
Through these experiments it was shown that the living forms
continuously change in the course of their propagation. Under certain
circumstances some living organisms change so much after a few
generations that in comparing the newly bred forms with their
ancestors, one could speak of two completely different species, each
of which follows its own design of organization. Such a variability of
forms is used by the breeder in order to develop organisms through
cultivation that answer certain demands. A breeder can produce a
species of sheep with an especially fine wool if he allows only those
specimens of his flock to be propagated that have the finest wool. The
quality of the wool is then improved in the course of the generations.
After some time, a species of sheep is obtained which, in the
formation of its wool, has progressed far beyond its ancestors. The
same is true with other qualities of living organisms. Two conclusions
can be drawn from this fact. The first is that nature has the tendency
to change living beings; the second, that a quality that has begun to
change in a certain direction increases in that direction, if in the
process of propagation of organic beings those specimens that do not
have this quality are excluded. The organic forms then assume other
qualities in the course of time, and continue in the direction of
their change once this process has begun. They change and transmit the
changed qualities to their descendants.
The natural conclusion from this observation is that change and
hereditary transmission are two driving principles in the evolution of
organic beings. If it is to be assumed that in the natural course of
events in the world, formations that are adapted to life come into
being side by side with those not adapted as well as others, it must
also be supposed that the struggle for life takes place in the most
diversified forms. This struggle effects, without a plan, what the
breeder does with the aid of a preconceived plan. As the breeder
excludes the specimen from the process of propagation that would
introduce undesired qualities into the development, so the struggle
for life eliminates the unfit. Only the fit survive in evolution. The
tendency for perpetual perfection enters thus into the evolutionary
process like a mechanical law. After Darwin had seen this and after he
had thereby laid a firm foundation to a naturalistic world conception,
he could write the enthusiastic words at the end of his work, The
Origin of Species, which introduced a new epoch of thought:
Thus, from the war of nature, from famine and death the most exalted
object which we are capable of conceiving, namely, the production of
the higher animals, directly follows. There is grandeur in this view
of life, with its several powers having been originally breathed by
the Creator into a few forms or into one; and that, whilst this planet
has gone cycling on according to the fixed law of gravity, from so
simple a beginning endless forms most beautiful and most wonderful
have been and are being evolved.
At the same time one can see from this sentence that Darwin does not
derive his conception from any anti-religious sentiment but merely
from the conclusions that for him follow from distinctly significant
facts. It was not hostility against the needs of religious experience
that persuaded him to a rational view of nature, for he tells us
distinctly in his book how this newly acquired world of ideas appeals
to his heart.
Authors of the highest eminence seem to be fully satisfied with the
view that each species has been independently created. To my mind it
accords better with what we know of the laws impressed in matter by
the Creator that the production and extinction of the past and present
inhabitants of the world should have been due to secondary causes,
like those determining the birth and death of the individual. When I
view all beings not as special creations, but as the linear
descendants of some few beings which lived long before the first bed
of the Cambrian system was deposited, they seem to me to become
ennobled. . . . Hence, we may look with some confidence to a secure
future of great length. And as natural selection works solely by and
for the good of each being, all corporeal and mental endowments will
tend to progress toward perfection.
Darwin showed in great detail how the organisms grow and spread, how,
in the course of their development, they transmit their properties
once they are acquired, how new organs are produced and change through
use or through lack of use, how in this way the organic beings are
adjusted to their conditions of existence and how finally through the
struggle for life a natural selection takes place by means of which an
ever increasing variety of more and more perfect forms come into
being.
In this way an explanation of teleologically adjusted beings seems to
be found that requires no other method for organic nature than that
which is used in inorganic nature. As long as it was impossible to
offer an explanation of this kind it had to be admitted, if one wanted
to be consistent, that everywhere in nature where a purpose-adjusted
being came into existence, the intervention of an extraneous power had
to be assumed. In every such case one had to admit a miracle.
Those who for decades before the appearance of Darwin's work had
endeavored to find a naturalistic world and life conception now felt
most vividly that a new direction of thought had been given. This
feeling is expressed by David Friedrich Strauss in his book,
The Old and the New Faith (1872).
One sees this is the way it must go; this is where the new banner is
waving sprightly in the wind. It is a real joy in the sense of the
loftiest joys of intellectual advance. We philosophers and critical
theologians talked and talked to discredit the idea of a miracle. Our
decree had no effect whatever, because we did not know how to
demonstrate this idea as a superfluous one, because we did not know
how to avoid it for we did not know of any energy of nature with which
we could replace it where it seemed to be most necessary to be
assumed. Darwin has demonstrated this energy of nature, this procedure
of nature; he has opened the door through which a fortunate posterity
will throw out the miracle once and for all times. Everyone who knows
how much depends on miracles will praise him for that deed as one of
the greatest benefactors of the human race.
Through Darwin's idea of fitness it is possible to think the concept
of evolution really in the form of a natural law. The old doctrine of
involution, which assumes that everything that comes into existence
has been there in a hidden form before (compare pages
in Part 1 Chapter IX),
had been deprived of its last hope with
this step. In the process of evolution as conceived by Darwin, the
more perfect form is in no way contained in the less perfect one, for
the perfection of a higher being comes into existence through
processes that have nothing whatsoever to do with the ancestors of
this being. Let us assume that a certain evolutionary series has
arrived at the marsupials. The form of the marsupials contains nothing
at all of a higher, more perfect form. It contains only the ability to
change at random in the course of its propagation. Certain
circumstances then come to pass that are independent of any
inner latent tendency of development of the form of the
marsupials but that are such that of all possible variations
(mutations) the pro-simians survive. The forms of the marsupials
contained that of the pro-simians no more than the direction of a
rolling billiard ball contains the path it will take after it has been
deflected from its original course by a second billiard ball.
Those accustomed to an idealistic mode of thinking had no easy time in
comprehending this reformed conception of evolution. Friedrich
Theodor Vischer, a man of extraordinary acumen and subtlety of
spirit who had come from Hegel's school, writes as late as 1874 in an
essay:
Evolution is an unfolding from a germ that proceeds from attempt to
attempt until the picture that the germ contained latently as a
possibility has become real. But once this is accomplished it stops
and holds on to the form that is found, keeping it as a permanent one.
Every concept as such would lose its firm outline if we were to
consider the types that have existed on our planet for so many
thousands of years as forever variable and above all if we were so to
consider our own human type. We should then be unable any longer to
trust our thoughts, the laws conceived by our thinking, our feelings,
the pictures of our imagination, all of which are nothing but the
clarifying imitations of forms of nature as it is known to us.
Everything becomes questionable.
In another passage in the same essay he says:
I still find it a little hard, for instance, to believe that we should
owe our eye to the process of seeing, our ear to that of hearing. The
extraordinary weight that is given to the process of natural selection
is something I am not quite satisfied with.
If Vischer had been asked whether or not he imagined that hydrogen and
oxygen contained within themselves in a latent form a picture of water
to make it possible for the latter to develop from the former, he
would undoubtedly have answered, No, neither in oxygen nor in
hydrogen is there anything contained of the water that is formed; the
conditions for the formation of this substance are given only when
hydrogen and oxygen are combined under certain circumstances. Is
the situation then necessarily different when, through the two factors
of the marsupials and the external conditions, the pro-simians came
into being? Why should the pro-simians be contained as a possibility,
as a scheme, in the marsupials in order to be capable of being
developed from them? What comes into being through evolution is
generated as a new formation without having been in existence in any
previous form.
Thoughtful naturalists felt the weight of the new teleological
doctrine no less than Strauss. Hermann Helmholtz belongs,
without doubt, among those who, in the eighteen-fifties and sixties,
could be considered as representatives of such thoughtful naturalists.
He stresses the fact that the wonderful purpose-conformity in the
structure of living organisms, which becomes increasingly apparent as
science progresses, challenges the comparison of all life processes to
human actions. For human actions are the only series of phenomena that
have a character that is similar to the organic ones. The fitness of
the arrangements in the world of organisms does, according to our
judgment, in most cases indeed far surpass what human intelligence is
capable of creating. It therefore cannot surprise us that it has
occurred to people to seek the origin of the structure and function of
the world of living beings in an intelligence far superior to that of
man. Helmholtz says:
Before Darwin one could admit two kinds of explanations for the fact
of organic purpose adjustment, both of which depended on an
interference of a free intelligence in the course of natural
phenomena. One either considered, according to the vitalistic theory,
the life-processes as perpetually guided by a life-soul; or one saw in
each species an act of a supernatural intelligence through which it
was supposed to have been generated. . . . Darwin's theory contains an
essentially new creative thought. It shows that a purpose-adjustment
of the form in the organisms can come to pass also without
interference of an intelligence through the random effect of a natural
law. This is the law of the transmission of individual peculiarities
from the parents to the descendants, a law that was long known and
recognized but was merely in need of a definite demarcation.
Helmholtz now is of the opinion that such a demarcation is given by
the principle of natural selection in the struggle for existence. A
scientist who, like Helmholtz, belongs to the most cautious
naturalists of that time, J. Henle, said in a lecture, If
the experiences of artificial breeding were to be applied to the
hypothesis of Oken and Lamarck, it would have to be shown how nature
proceeds in order to supply the mechanism through which the
experimental breeder obtains his result. This is the task Darwin set
for himself and that he pursued with admirable industry and
acumen.
The materialists were the ones who felt the greatest enthusiasm of all
from Darwin's accomplishment. They had long been convinced that sooner
or later a man like him would have to come along who would throw a
philosophical light on the vast field of accumulated facts that was so
much in need of a leading thought. In their opinion, the world
conception for which they had fought could not fail after Darwin's
discovery. Darwin approached his task as a naturalist. At first he
moved within the limits reserved to the natural scientist. That his
thoughts were capable of throwing a light on the fundamental problems
of world conception, on the question of man's relation to nature, was
merely touched upon in his book:
In the future I see open fields for far more important researches.
Psychology will be securely based on the foundation . . ., of the
necessary acquirement of each mental power and capacity by gradation.
Much light will be thrown on the origin of man and his history.
For the materialists, this question of the origin of man became, in
the words of Buechner, a matter of most intimate concern. In lectures
he gave in Offenbach during the winter of 1866 67, he says:
Must the theory of transformation also be applied to our own race?
Must it be extended to man, to us? Shall we have to submit to an
application of the same principles or rules that have caused the life
of all other organisms for the explanation of our own genesis and
origin? Or are we the lords of creation an exception?
Natural science clearly taught that man could not be an exception. On
the basis of exact anatomical investigations the English physiologist,
T. H. Huxley, wrote in his book, Man's Place in Nature (1863):
The critical comparison of all organs and their modification in the
series of the monkeys leads us to one and the same result, that the
anatomical differences that separate man from the gorilla and the
chimpanzee are not as great as the differences that separate the
anthropoid apes from the lower species of monkeys.
Could there still be a doubt in the face of such facts that natural
evolution had also produced man the same evolution that had caused
the series of organic beings as far as the monkey through growth,
propagation, inheritance, transmutation of forms and the struggle for
life?
During the course of the century this fundamental view penetrated more
and more into the mainstream of natural science. Goethe, to be sure,
had in his own way been convinced of this, and because of this
conviction he had most energetically set out to correct the opinion of
his contemporaries, which held that man lacked an intermaxillary bone
in his upper jaw. All animals were supposed to have this bone; only
man, so one thought, did not have it. In its absence one saw the proof
that man was anatomically different from the animals, that the plan of
his structure was to be thought along different lines. The
naturalistic mode of Goethe's thinking inspired him to undertake
elaborate anatomical studies to abolish this error. When he had
achieved this goal he wrote in a letter to Herder, convinced that he
had made a most important contribution to the knowledge of nature;
I compared the skulls of men and animals and I found the trail,
and behold, there it is. Now I ask you not to tell, for it must be
treated as a secret. But I want you to enjoy it with me, for it is
like the finishing stone in the structure of man; now it is complete
and nothing is lacking. Just see how it is!
Under the influence of such conceptions the great question of
philosophy of man's relation to himself and to the external world led
to the task of showing by the method of natural science what actual
process had led to the formation of man in the course of evolution.
Thereby the viewpoint from which one attempted to explain the
phenomena of nature changed. As long as one saw in every organism
including man the realization of a purposeful design of structure, one
had to consider this purpose also in the explanation of organic
beings. One had to consider that in the embryo the later organism is
potentially indicated. When this view was extended to the whole
universe, it meant that an explanation of nature fulfilled its task
best if it showed how the later stages of evolution with man as the
climax are prepared in the earlier stages.
The modern idea of evolution rejected all attempts of science to
recognize the potential later phases in the earlier stages.
Accordingly, the later phase was in no way contained in the earlier
one. Instead, what was gradually developed was the tendency to search
in the later phases for traces of the earlier ones. This principle
represented one of the laws of inheritance. One can actually speak of
a reversal of the tendency of explanation. This reversal became
important for ontogenesis, that is, for the formation of the ideas
concerning the evolution of the individual being from the egg to
maturity. Instead of showing the predisposition of the later organs in
the embryo, one set out to compare the various stages that an organism
goes through in the course of its individual evolution from the egg to
maturity with those of other forms of organisms. Lorenz Oken was
already moving in this direction. In the fourth volume of his
General History of Nature for All Classes of Readers he wrote:
Years ago, through my physiological investigations, I arrived at the
view that the developmental stages of the chicken in the egg have much
similarity with different classes of animals. In the beginning it
shows only the organs of infusoria, thereupon gradually assuming those
of the polyps, jellyfish, shellfish, snails and so forth. Conversely,
then, I also had to consider the classes of animals as evolutionary
stages that proceeded parallel to the developmental stages of the
chicken. This view of nature challenged me to the most minute
observation of those organs that are added as new forms to every
higher class of animal, as well as of the ones that are developed one
after the other during the developmental process. It is, of course,
not easy to establish a complete parallelism with such a difficult
object as a chick egg because its development is so incompletely
known. But to prove that the parallelism actually exists is indeed not
difficult. It is most distinctly shown in the transformation of the
insects, which is nothing more than the development of the young going
on before our eyes outside the egg, and actually in so slow a tempo
that we can observe and investigate every embryonic stage at our
leisure.
Oken compares the stages of transformation of the insects with the
other animals and finds that the caterpillars have a great similarity
with worms, and the cocoons with crustaceous animals. From such
similarities this ingenious thinker draws the conclusion that
there is, therefore, no doubt that we are here confronted with a
conspicuous similarity that justifies the idea that the evolutionary
history in the egg is nothing but a repetition of the history of the
creation of the animal classes. It came as a natural gift to
this brilliant man to apprehend a great idea for which he did not even
need the evidence of supporting facts. But it also lies in the nature
of such subtle ideas that they have no great effect on those who work
in the field of science. Oken appears like a comet on the firmament of
German philosophy. His thought supplies a flood of light. From a rich
treasure of ideas he suggests leading concepts for the most divergent
facts. His method of formulating factual connections, however, was
somewhat forced. He was too much preoccupied with the point he wanted
to make. This attitude also prevailed in his treatment of the law of
the repetition of certain animal forms in the ontogeny of others
mentioned above.
In contrast to Oken, Karl Ernst von Baer kept to the facts as
firmly as possible when he spoke, in his History of the Evolution
of Animals (1828), of the observations that had led Oken to his
idea:
The embryos of the mammals, birds, lizards and snakes, and probably
also those of the turtles, in their earlier stages are extraordinarily
similar to one another in their whole formation as well as in their
individual parts. These embryos are so similar in fact that they can
often only be distinguished by their sizes. I have in my possession
two little embryos in alcohol that I forgot to label, and now I cannot
possibly determine to what class they belong. They could be lizards,
little birds or young mammals, so similar is the head and trunk
formation of these animals. The extremities are still completely
absent in these embryos and, even if they were there, at the first
stages of their development they would not tell us anything because
the feet of lizards and mammals, the wings and feet of birds, as well
as the hands and feet of men, all develop from the same original form.
Such facts of embryological development excited the greatest interest
of those thinkers who tended toward Darwinism. Darwin had proven the
possibility of change in organic forms and, through transformation,
the species now in existence might possibly be descended from a few
original forms, or perhaps only one. Now it was shown that in their
first phases of development the various living organisms are so
similar to each other that they can scarcely be distinguished from one
another, if at all. These two ideas, the facts of comparative
embryology and the idea of descent, were organically combined in 1864
by Fritz Müller (1821 97) in his thoughtful essay, Facts
and Arguments for Darwin. Müller is one of those high-minded
personalities who needs a naturalistic world conception because they
cannot breathe spiritually without it. Also, in regard to his own
action, he would feel satisfaction only when he could feel that his
motivation was as necessary as a force of nature. In 1852 Müller
settled in Brazil. For twelve years he was a teacher at the gymnasium
in Desterro on the island of Santa Catharina, not far from the coast
of Brazil. In 1867 he had to give up this position. The man of the new
world conception had to give way to the reaction that, under the
influence of the Jesuits, took hold of his school. Ernst Haeckel has
described the life and activity of Fritz Müller in the Jenaische
Zeitschrift fur Naturwissenschaft (Vol. XXXI N.F. XXIV 1897).
Darwin called Müller the prince of observers, and the
small but significant booklet, Facts and Arguments for Darwin,
is the result of a wealth of observations. It deals with a
particular group of organic forms, the crustaceans, which are
radically different from one another in their maturity but are
perfectly similar at the time when they leave the egg. If one
presupposes, in the sense of Darwin's theory of descent, that all
crustacean forms have developed from one original type, and if one
accepts the similarity in the early stages as an inherited element of
the form of their common ancestor, one has thereby combined the ideas
of Darwin with those of Oken pertaining to the repetition of the
history of the creation of the animal species in the evolution of the
individual animal form. This combination was accomplished by Fritz
Müller. He thereby brought the earlier forms of an animal class into a
certain law-determined connection with the later ones, which, through
transformation, have formed out of them. The fact that at an earlier
stage the ancestral form of a being now living has had a particular
form caused its descendants at a later time to have another particular
form. By studying the stages of the development of an organism one
becomes acquainted with its ancestors whose nature has caused the
characteristics of the embryonic forms. Phylogenesis and ontogenesis
are, in Fritz Müller's book, connected as cause and effect. With this
step a new element had entered the Darwinian trend of ideas. This fact
retains its significance even though Müller's investigations of the
crustaceans were modified by the later research of Arnold Lang.
Only four years had passed since the appearance of Darwin's Origin
of the Species when Müller's book was published as its defense and
confirmation. Müller had shown how, with one special class of animals,
one should work in the spirit of the new ideas. Then, in 1866, seven
years after the Origin of the Species, a book appeared that
completely absorbed this new spirit. Using the ideas of Darwinism on a
high level of scientific discussion, it threw a great deal of light on
the problems of the interconnection of all life phenomena. This book
was Ernst Haeckel's General Morphology of Organisms. Every page
reflected his attempt to arrive at a comprehensive synopsis of the
totality of the phenomena of nature with the help of new thoughts.
Inspired by Darwinism, Haeckel was in search of a world conception.
Haeckel did his best in two ways to attempt a new world conception.
First, he continually contributed to the accumulation of facts that
throw light on the connection of the entities and energies of nature.
Second, with unbending consistency he derived from these facts the
ideas that were to satisfy the human need for explanation. He held the
unshakable conviction that from these facts and ideas man can arrive
at a fully satisfactory world explanation. Like Goethe, Haeckel was
convinced in his own way that nature proceeds in its work
according to eternal, necessary and thereby divine laws, so that
not even the deity could change it. Because this was clear to
him, he worshipped his deity in these eternal and necessary laws of
nature and in the substances in which they worked. As the harmony of
the natural laws, which are with necessity interconnected, satisfies
reason, according to his view, so it also offers to the feeling heart,
or to the soul that is ethically or religiously attuned, whatever it
may thirst for. In the stone that falls to the ground attracted by
gravity there is a manifestation of the same divine order that is
expressed in the blossom of a plant and in the human spirit that
created the drama of Wilhelm Tell.
How erroneous is the belief that the feeling for the wonderful beauty
of nature is destroyed by the penetration of reason into laws of
nature is vividly demonstrated in the work of Ernst Haeckel. A
rational explanation of nature had been declared to be incapable of
satisfying the needs of the soul. Wherever man is disturbed in his
inner life through knowledge of nature, it is not the fault of
knowledge but of man himself. His sentiments are developed in a wrong
direction. As we follow a naturalist like Haeckel without prejudice on
his path as an observer of nature, we feel our hearts beat faster. The
anatomical analysis, the microscopic investigation does not detract
from natural beauty but reveals a great deal more of it. There is no
doubt that there is an antagonism between reason and imagination,
between reflection and intuition, in our time. The brilliant essayist,
Ellen Key, is without doubt right in considering this antagonism as
one of the most important phenomena of our time (compare Ellen Key,
Essays, S. Fischer Verlag, Berlin, 1899). Whoever, like Ernst
Haeckel, digs deep into the treasure mine of facts, boldly emerges
with the thoughts resulting from these facts and climbs to the heights
of human knowledge, can see in the explanation of nature only an act
of reconciliation between the two contesting forces of reflection and
intuition that alternate in forcing each other into
submission (Ellen Key). Almost simultaneously with the
publication of the book in which Haeckel presented with unflinching
intellectual honesty his world conception derived from natural
science, that is, with the appearance of his Riddles of the
Universe in 1899, he began a serial publication called Artforms
of Nature. In it he gives pictures of the inexhaustible wealth of
wonderful formations that nature produces and that surpass by
far all artistic forms created by man in beauty and in variety.
The same man who introduces our mind to the law-determined order of
nature leads our imagination to the beauty of nature.
The need to bring the great problems of world conception into direct
contact with scientific, specialized research led Haeckel to one of
the facts concerning which Goethe said that they represent the
significant points at which nature yields the fundamental ideas for
its explanation of its own accord, meeting us halfway in our search.
This was realized by Haeckel as he investigated how Oken's thesis,
which Fritz Müller had applied to the crustaceans, could be fruitfully
applied to the whole animal kingdom. In all animals except the
Protista, which are one-celled organisms, a cup- or jug-shaped body,
the gastrula, develops from the zygote with which the organism begins
its ontogenesis. This gastrula is an animal form that is to be found
in the first stages of development of all animals from the sponges to
man. It consists merely of skin, mouth and stomach. There is a low
class of zoophytes that possess only these organs during their lives
and therefore resemble gastrulae. This fact is interpreted by Haeckel
from the point of view of the theory of descent. The gastrula form is
an inherited form that the animal owes to the form of its common
ancestor. There had been, probably millions of years before, a species
of animals, the gastrae, that was built in a way similar to that of
the lower zoophytes still living today the sponges, polyps, etc.
From this animal species all the various forms living today, from the
polyps, sponges, etc., to man, repeat this original form in the course
of their ontogenies.
In this way an idea of gigantic scope had been obtained. The path
leading from the simple to the complicated, to the perfect form in the
world of organisms, was thereby indicated in its tentative outline. A
simple animal form develops under certain circumstances. One or
several individuals of this form change to another form according to
the conditions of life to which they are exposed. What has come into
existence through this transmutation is again transmitted to
descendants. There are then two different forms, the old one that has
retained the form of the first stage, and a new one. Both of these
forms can develop in different directions and into different degrees
of perfection. After long periods of time an abundant wealth of
species comes into existence through the transmission of the earlier
form and through new formations by means of the process of adaptation
to the conditions of life.
In this manner Haeckel connects today's processes in the world of
organisms with the events of primeval times. If we want to explain
some organ of an animal of the present age, we look back to the
ancestors that had developed this organ under the circumstances in
which they lived. What has come into existence through natural causes
in earlier times has been handed down to our time through the process
of heredity. Through the history of the species the evolution of the
individual receives its explanation. The phylogenesis, therefore,
contains the causes for the ontogenesis. Haeckel expresses this fact
in his fundamental law of biogenetics: The short ontogenesis or
development of the individual is a rapid and brief repetition, an
abbreviated recapitulation of the long process of phylogenesis, the
development of the species.
Through this law every attempt at explanation through special
purposes, all teleology in the old sense, has been eliminated. One no
longer looks for the purpose of an organ; one looks for the causes
through which it has developed. A given form does not point to a goal
toward which it strives, but toward the origin from which it sprang.
The method of explanation for the organic phenomena has become the
same as that for the inorganic. Water is not considered the aim of
oxygen, nor is man considered the purpose of creation. Scientific
research is directed toward the origin of, and the actual cause for,
living beings. The dualistic mode of conception, which declares that
the organic and the inorganic has to be explained according to two
different principles, gives way to a monistic mode of conception, to a
monism that has only one uniform mode of explanation for the whole of
nature.
Haeckel characteristically points out that through his discovery the
method has been found through which every dualism in the
above-mentioned sense must be overcome.
Phylogenesis is the mechanical cause of ontogenesis. With this
statement our basically monistic conception of organic evolution is
clearly characterized, and on the truth of this principle depends
primarily the truth of the gastraea theory. . . . Every naturalist,
who in the field of biogenesis is not satisfied with a mere admiration
of strange phenomena but strives for an understanding of their
significance, will, in the future, either have to side with or against
this principle. It marks at the same time the complete break that
separates the older teleological and dualistic morphology from the new
mechanical and monistic one. If the physiological functions of
inheritance and adaptation have been proven to be the only causes of
the process of organic formation, then every kind of teleology, of
dualistic and metaphysical mode of conception has thereby been
eliminated from the field of biogenesis; the sharp contrast between
the leading principles is clearly marked. Either a direct and causal
connection between ontogeny and phylogeny exists or it does not. There
is no third possibility! Either epigenesis and descent, or
pre-formation and creation! (Compare also
in Part 1 Chapter IX
of this book.)
After Haeckel had absorbed Darwin's view of the origin of man he
defended forcefully the conclusion that must be drawn from it. It was
impossible for him just to hint hesitatingly, like Darwin, at this
problem of all problems. Anatomically and physiologically
man is not distinguishable from the higher animals. Therefore, the
same origin must be attributed to him as to them. Haeckel boldly
defended this opinion and the consequences that followed from it for
the conception of the world. There was no doubt for him that in the
future the highest manifestations of man's life, the activities of his
spirit, were to be considered under the same viewpoint as the function
of the simplest living organism. The observation of the lowest
animals, the protozoa, infusoria, rhizopods, taught him that these
organisms had a soul. In their motions, in the indications of the
sensations they show, he recognized manifestations of life that only
had to be increased and perfected in order to develop into man's
complicated actions of reason and will.
Beginning with the gastraea, which lived millions of years ago, what
steps does nature take to arrive at man? This was the comprehensive
question as stated by Haeckel. He supplied the answer in his
Anthropogenesis, which appeared in 1874. In its first part,
this book deals with the history of the individual (ontogenesis), in
the second part, with that of the species (phylogenesis). He showed
point by point how the latter contains the causes of the former. Man's
position in nature had thereby been determined according to the
principles of the theory of descent. To works like Haeckel's
Anthropogenesis, the statement that the great anatomist,
Karl Gegenbaur, made in his Comparative Anatomy (1870)
can be justly applied. He wrote that in exchange for the method of
investigation Darwin gave to science with his theory he received in
return clarity and firmness of purpose. In Haeckel's view, the method
of Darwinism had also supplied science with the theory of the origin
of man.
What actually was accomplished by this step can be appreciated in its
full measure only if one looks at the opposition with which Haeckel's
comprehensive application of the principles of Darwinism was received
by the followers of idealistic world conceptions. It is not even
necessary to quote those who, blindly believing in the traditional
opinion, turned against the monkey theory, or those who
believed that all finer, higher morality would be endangered if men
were no longer convinced that they had a purer, higher
origin. Other thinkers, although quite open-minded with regard
to new truths, found it difficult to accept this new truth.
They asked themselves the question, Do we not deny our own
rational thinking if we no longer look for its origin in a general
world reason over us, but in the animal kingdom below?
Mentalities of this sort eagerly attacked the points where Haeckel's
view seemed to be without support of the facts. They had powerful
allies in a number of natural scientists who, through a strange bias,
used their factual knowledge to emphasize the points where actual
experience was still insufficient to prove the conclusions drawn by
Haeckel. The typical, and at the same time the most impressive,
representative of this viewpoint of the naturalists was Rudolf
Virchow (1821 1902). The opposition of Virchow and Haeckel can
be characterized as follows. Haeckel puts his trust in the inner
consistency of nature, concerning which Goethe is of the opinion that
it is sufficient to make up for man's inconsistency. Haeckel,
therefore, argues that if a principle of nature has been verified for
certain cases, and if we still lack the experience to show its
validity in other cases, we have no reason to hold the progress of our
knowledge back. What experience denies us today, it may yield
tomorrow. Virchow is of the opposite opinion. He wants to yield as
little ground as possible to a comprehensive principle. He seems to
believe that life for such a principle cannot be made hard enough. The
antagonism between these two spirits was brought to a sharp point at
the Fiftieth Congress of German naturalists and doctors in 1877.
Haeckel read a paper there on the topic, The Theory of Evolution of
Today in Its Relation to Science in General.
In 1894 Virchow felt that he had to state his view in the following
way. Through speculation one has arrived at the monkey theory;
one could just as well have ended up with an elephant theory or a
sheep theory. What Virchow demanded was incontestable proof of
this theory. As soon as something turned up that fitted as a link in
the chain of the argumentation, Virchow attempted to invalidate it
with all means at his disposal.
Such a link in the chain of proof was presented with the bone remnants
that Eugen Dubois had found in Java in 1894. They consisted of a skull
and thigh bone and several teeth. Concerning this find, an interesting
discussion arose at the Congress of Zoologists at Leyden. Of twelve
zoologists, three were of the opinion that these bones came from a
monkey and three thought they came from a human being; six, however,
believed they presented a transitional form between man and monkey.
Dubois shows in a convincing manner in what relation the being whose
bone remnants were under discussion stood to the present monkey, on
the one hand, and to man of today, on the other. The theory of
evolution of natural science must claim such intermediary forms. They
fill the holes that exist between numerous forms of organisms. Every
new intermediary form constitutes a new proof for the kinship of all
living organisms. Virchow objected to the view that these bone
remnants came from such an intermediary form. At first, he declared
that it was the skull of a monkey and the thigh bone of a man. Expert
paleontologists, however, firmly pronounced, according to the careful
report, on the finding, that the remnants belonged together. Virchow
attempted to support his view that the thigh bone could be only that
of a human being with the statement that a certain growth in the bone
proved that it must have had a disease that could only have been
healed through careful human attention. The paleontologist, Marsch,
[e.Ed: perhaps American paleontologist, Othniel Charles Marsh
(1831 1899)]
however, maintained that similar bone extuberances occurred in wild
animals as well. A further statement of Virchow's, that the deep
incision between the upper rim of the eye socket and the lower skull
cover of the alleged intermediary form proved it to be the skull of a
monkey was then contradicted by the naturalist Nehring, who claimed
that the same formation was found in a human skull from Santos,
Brazil. Virchow's objections came from the same turn of mind that also
caused him to consider the famous skulls of Neanderthal, Spy, etc., as
pathological formations, while Haeckel's followers regarded them as
intermediary forms between monkey and man.
Haeckel did not allow any objections to deprive him of his confidence
in his mode of conception. He continued his scientific work without
swerving from the viewpoints at which he had arrived, and through
popular presentations of his conception of nature, he influenced the
public consciousness. In his book, Systematic Phylogenesis, Outline
of a Natural System of Organisms on the Basis of the History of
Species (1894 96), he attempted to demonstrate the natural
kinship of organisms in a strictly scientific method. In his
Natural History of Creation, which, from 1868 1908, appeared
in eleven editions, he gave a popular explanation of his views. In
1899, in his popular studies on monistic philosophy entitled, The
Riddles of the Universe, he gave a survey of his ideas in natural
philosophy by demonstrating without reserve the many applications of
his basic thoughts. Between all these works he published studies on
the most diverse specialized researches, always paying attention at
the same time to the philosophical principles and the scientific
knowledge of details.
The light that shines out from the monistic world conception is,
according to Haeckel's conviction, to disperse the heavy clouds
of ignorance and superstition that have heretofore spread an
impenetrable darkness over the most important one of all problems of
human knowledge, that is, the problem concerning man's origin, his
true nature and his position in nature. This is what he said in
a speech given August 26, 1898 at the Fourth International Congress of
Zoologists in Cambridge, On Our Present Knowledge Concerning the
Origin of Man. In what respect his world conception forms a bond
between religion and science, Haeckel has shown in an impressive way
in his book, Monism as a Bond between Religion and Science, Credo
of a Naturalist, which appeared in 1892.
If one compares Haeckel with Hegel, one can see distinctly the
difference in the tendencies of world conception in the two halves of
the nineteenth century. Hegel lives completely in the idea and accepts
only as much as he needs from the world of facts for the illustration
of his idealistic world picture. Haeckel is rooted with every fiber of
his being in the world of facts, and he derives from this world only
those ideas toward which these facts necessarily tend. Hegel always
attempts to show that all beings tend to reach their climax of
evolution in the human spirit; Haeckel continuously endeavors to prove
that the most complicated human activities point back to the simplest
origins of existence. Hegel explains nature from the spirit; Haeckel
derives the spirit from nature. We can, therefore, speak of a reversal
of the thought direction in the course of the century. Within German
intellectual life, Strauss, Feuerbach and others began this process of
reversal. In their materialism the new direction found a provisional
extreme expression, and in Haeckel's thought world it found a strictly
methodical-scientific one. For this is the significant thing in
Haeckel, that all his activity as a research worker is permeated by a
philosophical spirit. He does not at all work toward results that for
some philosophical motivation or other are considered to be the aim of
his world conception or of his philosophical thinking. What is
philosophical about him is his method. For him, science itself has the
character of a world conception. His very way of looking at things
predestines him to be a monist. He looks upon spirit and nature with
equal love. For this reason he could find spirit in the simplest
organism. He goes even further than that. He looks for the traces of
spirit in the inorganic particles of matter:
Every atom possesses an inherent quantity of energy and in this sense
is animate. Without assuming a soul for the atom, the simplest and
most general phenomena of chemistry are unexplainable. Pleasure and
displeasure, desire and aversion, attraction and repulsion must be a
common property of all material atoms. For the motion of the atoms,
which must take place in the formation and dissolution of every
chemical compound can only be explained if we assume that they have
sensation and will. On this assumption the generally accepted chemical
doctrine of affinity is really based.
As he traces spirit down to the atom so he follows the purely material
mechanism of events up to the most lofty accomplishments of the
spirit:
The spirit and soul of man are also nothing else but energies that are
inseparably bound to the material substratum of our bodies. As the
motion of our flesh is bound to the form elements of our muscles, so
our mind's power of thinking is bound to the form elements of our
brains. Our spiritual energies are simply functions of these physical
organs just as every energy is a function of a material body.
One must not confuse this mode of conception with one that dreams
souls in a hazy mystical fashion into the entities of nature and then
assumes that they are more or less similar to that of man. Haeckel is
a strict opponent of a world conception that projects qualities and
activities of man into the external world. He has repeatedly expressed
his condemnation of the humanization of nature, of anthropomorphism,
with a clarity that cannot be misunderstood. If he attributes
animation to inorganic matter, or to the simplest organisms, he means
by that nothing more than the sum of energy manifestations that we
observe in them. He holds strictly to the facts. Sensation and will
are for him no mystical soul energies but are nothing more
than what we observe as attraction and repulsion. He does not mean to
say that attraction and repulsion are really sensation and
will. What he means is that attraction and repulsion are on the lowest
stage what sensation and will are on a higher one. For evolution is
for him not merely an unwrapping of the higher stages of the spiritual
out of the lower forms in which they are already contained in a hidden
fashion, but a real ascent to new formations, an intensification of
attraction and repulsion into sensation and will (compare prior comments
in this Chapter).
This fundamental view of Haeckel agrees in a certain way with that of
Goethe. He states in this connection that he had arrived at the
fulfillment of his view of nature with his insight into the two
great springs of all nature, namely, polarity and
intensification (Polarität und Steigerung), polarity
belonging to matter insofar as we think of it materially,
intensification insofar as we think of it spiritually. The former is
engaged in the everlasting process of attraction and repulsion, the
latter in a continual intensification. As matter can never be and act
without spirit, however, nor spirit without matter, so matter can also
be intensified and the spirit will never be without attraction and
repulsion.
A thinker who believes in such a world conception is satisfied to
explain by other such things and processes, the things and processes
that are actually in the world. The idealistic world conceptions need,
for the derivation of a thing or process, entities that cannot be
found within the realm of the factual. Haeckel derives the form of the
gastrula that occurs in the course of animal evolution from an
organism that he assumes really existed at some time. An idealist
would look for ideal forces under the influence of which the
developing germ becomes the gastrula. Haeckel's monism draws
everything he needs for the explanation of the real world from the
same real world. He looks around in the world of the real in order to
recognize in which way the things and processes explain one another.
His theories do not have the purpose for him, as do those of the
idealist, to find a higher element in addition to the factual
elements, but they merely serve to make the connection of the facts
understandable. Fichte, the idealist, asked the question of man's
destination. He meant by that something that cannot be completely
presented in the form of the real, the factual; something that reason
has to produce as an addition to the factually given existence, an
element that is to make the real existence of man translucent by
showing it in a higher light. Haeckel, the monistic contemplator of
the world, asks for the origin of man, and he means by that the
factual origin, the lower organism out of which man had developed
through actual processes.
It is characteristic that Haeckel argues for the animation of the
lower organisms. An idealist would have resorted to rational
conclusions. He would present necessities of thought. Haeckel refers
to what he has seen.
Every naturalist, who, like me, has observed for many years the life
activities of the one-celled protozoa, is positively convinced that
they, too, possess a soul. This cellular soul consists also of a sum
of sensations, perceptions and will activities; sensation, thinking
and will of our human souls differ from those of the cellular soul
only in degree.
The idealist attributes spirit to matter because he cannot accept the
thought that spirit can develop from mere matter. He believes that one
would have to deny the spirit if one does not assume it to exist
before its appearance in forms of existence without organs, without
brains. For the monist, such thoughts are not possible. He does not
speak of an existence that is not manifested externally as such. He
does not attribute two kinds of properties to things: those that are
real and manifested in them and those that in a hidden way are latent
in them only to be revealed at a higher stage of development. For him,
there is what he observes, nothing else, and if the object of
observation continues its evolution and reaches a higher stage in the
course of its development, then these later forms are there
only in the moment when they become visible.
How easily Haeckel's monism can be misunderstood in this direction is
shown by the objections that were made by the brilliant thinker,
Bartholomaeus von Carneri (1821 1909), who made lasting
contributions for the construction of an ethics of this world
conception. In his book, Sensations and Consciousness, Doubts
Concerning Monism (1893), he remarks that the principle, No
spirit without matter, but also no matter without spirit, would
justify our extending this question to the plant and even to the next
rock we may stumble against, and to attribute spirit also to them.
Without doubt such a conclusion would lead to a confusion of
distinctions. It should not be overlooked that consciousness arises
only through the cell activity in the cerebrum. The conviction
that there is no spirit without matter, that is to say, that all
spiritual activity is bound to a material activity, the former
terminating with the latter, is based on experience, while there is no
experience for the statement that there is always spirit connected
with matter. Somebody who would want to attribute animation to
matter that does not show any trace of spirit would be like one who
attributed the function to indicate time not to the mechanism of a
watch but to the metal out of which it is made.
Properly understood, Haeckel's view is not touched by Carneri's
criticism. It is safe from this criticism because Haeckel holds
himself strictly within the bounds of observation. In his Riddles
of the Universe, he says, I, myself, have never defended the
theory of atom-consciousness. I have, on the contrary, expressly
emphasized that I think the elementary psychic activities of sensation
and will, which are attributed to the atoms, as unconscious.
What Haeckel wants is only that one should not allow a break in the
explanation of natural phenomena. He insists that one should trace
back the complicated mechanism by which spirit appears in the brain,
to the simple process of attraction and repulsion of matter.
Haeckel considers the discovery of the organs of thought by Paul
Flechsig to be one of the most important accomplishments of modern
times. Flechsig had pointed out that in the gray matter of the brain
there are to be found the four seats of the central sense organs, or
four inner spheres of sensation, the spheres of touch,
smell, sight and hearing. Between the sense centers lie thought
centers, the real organs of mental life. They are the highest organs
of psychic activity that produce thought and consciousness. . . .
These four thought centers, distinguished from the intermediate sense
centers by a peculiar and highly elaborate nerve structure, are the
true organs of thought, the only organs of our consciousness.
Recently, Flechsig has proved that man has some especially complicated
structures in some of these organs that cannot be found in the other
mammals and that explain the superiority of human consciousness.
(Riddles of the Universe, Chapt. X.)
Passages like these show clearly enough that Haeckel does not intend
to assume, like the idealistic philosophers, the spirit as implicitly
contained in the lower stages of material existence in order to be
able to find it again on the higher stages. What he wanted to do was
to follow the simplest phenomena to the most complicated ones in his
observation, in order to show how the activity of matter, which in the
most primitive form is manifested in attraction and repulsion, is
intensified in the higher mental operations.
Haeckel does not look for a general spiritual principle for lack of
adequate general laws explaining the phenomena of nature and mind. So
far as his need is concerned, his general law is indeed perfectly
sufficient. The law that is manifested in the mental activities seems
to him to be of the same kind as the one that is apparent in the
attraction and repulsion of material particles. If he calls atoms
animated, this has not the same meaning that it would have if a
believer in an idealistic world conception did so. The latter would
proceed from the spirit. He would take the conceptions derived from
the contemplation of the spirit down into the simplest functions of
the atoms when he thinks of them as animated. He would explain thereby
the natural phenomena from entities that he had first projected into
them. Haeckel proceeds from the contemplation of the simplest
phenomena of nature and follows them up to the highest spiritual
activities. This means that he explains the spiritual phenomena from
laws that he has observed in the simplest natural phenomena.
Haeckel's world picture can take shape in a mind whose observation
extends exclusively to natural processes and natural entities. A mind
of this kind will want to understand the connection within the
realm of these events and beings. His ideal would be to see what the
processes and beings themselves reveal with respect to their
development and interaction, and to reject rigorously everything that
might be added in order to obtain an explanation of these processes
and activities. For such an ideal one is to approach all nature as one
would, for instance, proceed in explaining the mechanism of a watch.
It is quite unnecessary to know anything about the watchmaker, about
his skill and about his thoughts, if one gains an insight into the
mechanical actions of its parts. In obtaining this insight one has,
within certain limits, done everything that is admissible for the
explanation of the operation of the watch. One ought to be clear about
the fact that the watch itself cannot be explained if another method
of explanation is admitted, as, for instance, if somebody thought of
some special spiritual forces that move the hour and minute hands
according to the course of the sun. Every suggestion of a special life
force, or of a power that works toward a purpose within
the organisms, appears to Haeckel as an invented force that is added
to the natural processes. He is unwilling to think about the natural
processes in any other way than by what they themselves disclose to
observation. His thought structure is to be derived directly
from nature.
In observing the evolution of world conception, this thought structure
strikes us, as it were, as the counter-gift from the side of natural
science to the Hegelian world conception, which accepts in its thought
picture nothing from nature but wants everything to originate
from the soul. If Hegel's world conception said that the
self-conscious ego finds itself in the experience of pure thought,
Haeckel's view of nature could reply that the thought experience is a
result of the nature processes, is, indeed, their highest product. If
the Hegelian world conception would not be satisfied with such a
reply, Haeckel's naturalistic view could demand to be shown some inner
thought experience that does not appear as if it were a mirror
reflection of events outside thought life. In answer to this demand, a
philosophy would have to show how thought can come to life in the soul
and can really produce a world that is not merely the intellectual
shadow of the external world. A thought that is merely thought, merely
the product of thinking, cannot be used as an effective objection to
Haeckel's view. In the comparison mentioned above, he would maintain
that the watch contains nothing in itself that allows a conclusion as
to the personality, etc., of the watchmaker. Haeckel's naturalistic
view tends to show that, as long as one is merely confronted with
nature, one cannot make any statement concerning nature except what it
records. In this respect this naturalistic conception is significant
as it appears in the course of the development of world conception. It
proves that philosophy must create a field for itself that lies
in the realm of spontaneous creativity of thought life beyond the
thoughts that are gained from nature.
Philosophy must take the step beyond Hegel that was pointed out in a
previous chapter. It cannot consist of a method that moves in
the same field with natural science. Haeckel himself probably felt not
the slightest need to pay any attention to such a step of philosophy.
His world conception does bring thoughts to life in the soul, but only
insofar as their life has been stimulated by the observation of
natural processes. The world picture that thought can create when it
comes to life in the soul without this stimulus represents the kind of
higher world conception that would adequately complement Haeckel's
picture of nature. One has to go beyond the facts that are directly
contained in the watch if one wants to know, for instance, something
about the form of the watchmaker's face. But, for this reason, one has
no right to demand that Haeckel's naturalistic view itself should not
speak as Haeckel does when he states what positive facts he has
observed concerning natural processes and natural beings.
|