Foreword
It is fair to warn the reader
that this is not an easy book. Should he be broaching the territory,
without any previous knowledge of Rudolf Steiner's work and techniques,
simply as one option in his search for a convincing critique of the
prevalent materialism (or, as it is more commonly called, reductionism),
he might do better to begin with one or both of two other books by the
same author, The Origins of Natural Science and The Boundaries
of Natural Science. There is little doubt that dissatisfaction
with reductionism is gradually becoming more widespread (compare the
tiny minority that was touched by it in the Victorian age); and it is
perhaps significant that another change in the current world-view appears
to be accompanying it. I mean an increasingly wide acceptance of the
notion that human consciousness itself is in process of evolution; that
there has not merely been a ‘progress’ from one set of ideas
(largely erroneous) about the nature of the world and humanity towards
a more ‘advanced’ one, but that the very structure of consciousness,
the whole relation between man and nature, has been changing through
the millennia.
Nowhere is this perspective,
and the revised cosmology it entails, more explicit than in the literary
legacy of Rudolf Steiner, and nowhere is its importance more earnestly
stressed. The title of the present work already contains the difference
between evolution of consciousness and history of ideas. History is
the record of a conscious process, and the term is often extended to
signify the process itself. Evolution is a process occurring at a pre-conscious
stage, and up to the present this has applied also to the evolution
of consciousness. Thus, the karma of materialism is not the same as
the history of materialism. Karma is the name of a process operating
at an unconscious level in the development of a human individuality,
a process normally observable only in its effects; and the Karma of
materialism is such a process operating in the development of materialism.
So underneath the history of materialism (which would amount to a history
of ideas, culminating in reductionism) Steiner reveals an unconscious
process extending both before and after that history. Reductionism as
theory manifests first in natural science, but the change of consciousness
underlying it began much earlier, and it continues now irrespective
of theory and affects the whole life of humanity. These lectures were
delivered in the year 1917, when the catalogue of global disasters,
which Steiner saw as the Karma of materialism, was still not long past
its dawn; and it is with the effects of materialism in the social and
political life, of humanity, both national and international, that they
mainly concern themselves.
Just as in Boundaries
of Natural Science Rudolf Steiner argues the necessity of penetrating
this hitherto unconscious realm for the future health of science itself,
so here he argues its necessity in order to cope with social and political
problems that are growing more and more intractable as they are less
and less understood. Penetrating it with what? With strengthened and
energetic thinking. Notwithstanding his admiration for the achievements
of natural science, disciplined as it is by its constant relation to
observable fact, he accuses it of one disastrous oversight. While it
has devised and continues to devise ever more elaborate and more precise
tools for investigation, it has left unexamined and unimproved the first
and most essential, the most ubiquitously applied, of all its tools.
It has never tried to examine the nature of thinking itself; the point
at which unconscious process blossoms into, or rather “sets”
as, conscious thought. In the Boundaries course Steiner describes
a method by which scientists could embark on such an examination. Here
he is more concerned with the effects that have stemmed from their failure
to do so at the time of the scientific revolution and after it. This
involves reverting to that period in history and to the period preceding
it. It is no use just saying: yes, there has been an evolution of consciousness,
and it has resulted in materialism. It is no use simply chronicling
effects; the process itself must be penetrated, and penetrated in detail;
and if this entails reference to the thought processes of such historical
figures as Thomas Aquinas and Martin Luther, so be it.
The first step however is
to delineate the process itself, as far as possible, and this he does
in Lecture III by way of a careful treatment, both synchronic and diachronic,
of the relation between intellect, perception and
breathing. The lecture should be read carefully, for it is
there that he lays the foundation for the doctrine which he will go
on to inculcate. Namely, that the unconscious is not just ‘spirit’
(still less of course the Freudian psycho-physical jumble); nor is it
simply an inferred and unknowable 'world of spirit'; it is a world of
active spiritual beings, whose particular aims and influences are not
wholly, and will become less and less, beyond the reach of human knowledge.
Or perhaps it would be truer
to say the doctrine which he will go on to assume. That is one of the
reasons why it is a difficult book, not simply because such an immaterial
cosmology is repugnant to the contemporary mind-set: for repugnant it
certainly is, except to a level of open-mindedness that is deplorably
rare. Open-mindedness at a somewhat lower level is not so infrequent.
There are many minds in our time acutely aware of the apparent impotence
of the human spirit to deal with the complex and apparently insoluble
problems that increasingly threaten its continued existence, and which
go so far as to proclaim that a new kind of consciousness seems to be
demanded of us. What is wanted, these uneasy people say, is altogether
new ideas, a new kind of thinking. But they usually forget that the
new is by definition unfamiliar; so that, when they are confronted with
a picture of the universe that is not just a rearrangement of the old
picture, but is really new and therefore wholly unfamiliar, they are
offended or contemptuous. It becomes clear, Steiner repeats with emphasis
and with examples to drive it home, that what they really wanted was
something that looks new but is in fact old enough to feel quite comfortable.
Confronted by anything beyond that they refuse even to examine the evidence
for it. Exclamation marks are a sufficient refutation.
For many readers there will
be the added difficulty of what they will feel as its author's tendency
to plunge in medias res. Quite early in the book they will
be confronted by references to named spiritual beings to whom they have
not been introduced, notably certain of the spiritual hierarchies, who
have been differently named in different traditions, but for whom Steiner
uses the nomenclature found with their earliest recorded appearance
in the extant literature of the West, that is the work of ‘pseudo-Dionysius’;
and, over and above these, to the 'adversary' figures of Lucifer and
Ahriman, especially the latter. If the reader is wise, he will reflect
that, where knowledge of the immaterial itself is at issue, and not
simply knowledge of its material effects, it is the same as with all
knowledge. Neither things nor beings can be spoken of without being
identified, or identified without being named: It remains true that
some previous acquaintance with the literature of Steiner's anthroposophy
will greatly reduce this difficulty, and will prevent the names being
merely names. Nor is there much doubt that most of his original
audience enjoyed such an acquaintance.
Some acquaintance then
with the literature of anthroposophy is desirable in a reader of this
book. But I would not say it is indispensable. There is another way
of acquainting oneself with unfamiliar terminology besides starting
with a set of definitions. Indeed definitions, though useful in forestalling
error, may even hinder close acquaintance with the actuality of what
is defined, inasmuch as they tend to substitute abstraction for experience.
The other way of twigging the meanings of unfamiliar words is to plunge
into contexts wherein they occur more than once, and sometimes perhaps
by way of casual reference, and thus gradually to approach nearer and
nearer to them by experiencing their use in those contexts. Incidentally
if this way were not a way that is wide open to us, we should never
have learned to speak or to understand anything at all.
I believe therefore that
readers will not be lacking who will by-pass any initial stumbling-blocks
as they enter into the substance of the book and become more and more
impressed by its whole tone, by the authority born of wide learning,
long reflection and exceptional insight and by the profound sense of
responsibility, alike to the truth and to humanity, that breathe through
its wide-ranging paragraphs.
Owen Barfield
|